Epiphanies, Individuation, and Human Flourishing Essays On Nature, Beauty, and Art, 1st Edition
Epiphanies, Individuation, and Human Flourishing Essays On Nature, Beauty, and Art, 1st Edition
Visit the link below to download the full version of this book:
https://medidownload.com/product/epiphanies-individuation-and-human-flourishing-
essays-on-nature-beauty-and-art-1st-edition/
Introduction 1
4 Art and Its Functions: Some Comments About Freud and Jung 60
Our human consciousness and what ‘it’ is, remains a mystery that so far has eluded
us, something about which we remain largely ignorant, even with recent insights.
This is not, from a scientific point of view, wilful ignorance. No-one knows or
has discovered the key to this mystery although there are many well thought-
out guesses based on research and argument, many beliefs, many attempts to cap-
ture consciousness (Blackmore, 2005; Dennett, 1992; Metzinger, 2009; Prinz &
Oxford University, 2015). So, many theories about mind, consciousness, the brain
have emerged with the development of neuroscience over the past 60 years. On
one account, the mind and/or consciousness can be thought of as function: con-
sciousness is the way in which the brain functions (Levin, Fall 2018).1 Or, per-
haps the brain can be thought of as a sophisticated computational system like a
Turing machine or a system of neural networks (Rescorla, 2020). Or, the mind
and consciousness might emerge from the way that the brain is as either a parallel
or supervenient system (Stoljar, 2020). Or, consciousness might defy the attempts
of neuroscientists and philosophers and remain as a hard problem, the hard problem
or question (Chalmers, 1995, 1996, 2018). This focus on the nature of conscious-
ness (or even its mention) has been a fairly recent development in analytic Anglo-
American philosophy. When I was a young student, it was the mind that occupied
pride of place in theorising human being. That said, Indian philosophies have taken
consciousness very seriously for a very long time. In Europe, phenomenology and
existential philosophies, and of course, psychiatry and psychology have been the
trendsetters in this domain. That said, the mechanism, if there is one and whatever
it is, of awareness and self-consciousness exceeds our current knowledge or is even
unknowable, something many of us are too proud to admit—that there are limits to
human knowledge and even experience.
So we are in a position in which the scientific and philosophical literature on
consciousness, bodies, brains, and computers (specifically artificial intelligence in
Living Bodies and Consciousness ix
the case of the latter) is vast, often contradictory and argumentative, and comes to
different conclusions depending on the model developed and explored (Berent,
2020; Churchland, 2007; Churchland & Sejnowski, 2017; Colombetti, 2014; Currie
& Ravenscroft, 2002; Dennett, 1992; Gallagher, 2017; Goff, 2017, 2019; Heinämaa,
2007; Koch, 2012, 2019; Metzinger, 2009; Noë, 2016; Penfield, 2015; Penrose, 2016;
Prinz, 2012; Prinz & Oxford University, 2015; Rescorla, 2020; Thompson & Varela,
2001; Zahavi, 2005, 2007).2 As I have indicated, the research is inconclusive, for
while neuroscience, for instance, might show us that the brain is involved in various
structural and functional activities of consciousness, it does not show us how these
activities produce imagination, and insight. Nor does the research show or explain
how it is that one can feel and know that one is feeling: there is little, if any,
definitive explanation of the meta-activities of consciousness, the hows and whys
of self-awareness. David Chalmers’ ‘the hard problem of consciousness’ (how come
I experience, how come my brain ‘produces’ both experience and me) remains.
Throughout this book, and given the above, I assume the following:
The word “soul,” here and elsewhere, simply translates Greek psuchē, and,
like that term, does not imply any particular metaphysical theory of the per-
sonality. It stands, simply, for all the life-activities of the creature; in the case of
Hellenistic contrasts between body and psuchē, it is especially important to
insist that no denial of physicalism need be involved, since both Epicureans
and Stoics are physicalists. The contrast is simply between the material
constituents of the organism and its life-activities, its states of awareness, and
so forth.
Nussbaum, 2013: 13
I follow suit, noting that I have questions rather than theories about the metaphys-
ical nature of personality.
I do not argue for any of these assumptions or points of view. In my opinion,
there is more missing than there is found and secured in scientific research and
phenomenological studies of human consciousness. So in what follows, there will
be reference to some of these views, and, hopefully, why I accept judiciously, and
perhaps tentatively, the above.
My own understanding of consciousness begins with the basic idea that con-
sciousness or awareness is responsiveness. Responsiveness to what? Consider this
Husserl takes up again the Critique of Judgement when he talks about a tele-
ology of consciousness. It is not a matter of duplicating human consciousness
with some absolute thought which, from outside, is imagined as assigning
to it its aims. It is a question of recognising consciousness itself as a
Living Bodies and Consciousness xi
Damasio goes on to explain that even if you and I form comparable images of an
object, it is because of the way in which our brains work, rather than mirror-like
fidelity to the outside world because we have no way of knowing whether or not
the image we form is an exact copy of that object, even though an ‘external reality’
might ‘prompt’ its creation. He argues for an interactionist view of the images
we form in our minds. This interaction between objects and the brain’s neural
activities is what creates those images of objects (Damasio, 2000: 320–321). I sus-
pect Damasio’s use echoes a ‘naturalised’ Kantian ontology. Immanuel Kant also
had argued representations and the faculty of representation (Vorstellungen) (Kant,
1933: 34, 75, 77 passim) related to his metaphysical distinction between appearances
and things-as-they-are. The point that Kant argues is that we humans do not have
an immediate and direct relationship with an external world, but that we represent
it to ourselves the world through appearances for which our minds and cognition
are responsible.5
It is clear that images and representations are closely linked. However, note that
Damasio’s rendering of ‘representation’ is visually oriented, even though his discus-
sion of ‘image’ invokes sound (Damasio, 2000: 318). This seems to be in keeping
with other work on the relationship between consciousness and the external world
and our experience of it in which work on consciousness and cognition focuses (no
pun intended) on vision, together with colour perception (Varela et al., 2016: 147 ff).
Even if it can be shown that many different factors affect colour perception it does
not follow that we are engaged in representation. What we touch and are touched
by, as I shall argue shortly, cuts across the idea of representation as outlined here.
In my view, we also have no way of knowing that images we form are not exact
copies, in some respects, of an object. This does not mean, though, that the mind
is always or is never a mirror image of the world we live in. We do not experience
the world in micro-detail. A snake about to strike me is a snake about to strike me,
just as lightning is lightning and death is death. From a phenomenological per-
spective, the world is as it is, unless we have clear reason to believe that is not the
case. The natural attitude, which can be thought of in terms of the world’s being
what we experience it to be, grounds our very understanding of ourselves and the
world. Of course we do make judgements, we can be right or wrong and we can
invoke the epoché as Edmund Husserl argued, to get at the essence of things. But on
an everyday basis, we are not mistaken for most of the time. We might hypothesise
and discover the subatomic world, but we cannot and do not experience that world
Living Bodies and Consciousness xiii
from the inside as it were. And we use the furniture of this world as we understand
and experience it, to make these hypotheses and discoveries (electron microscopes,
Large Hadron Collider). We shall come to this point again, in the next chapter.
For now, I maintain that our experience of the world gives us the best possible
idea of ourselves and our environment, importantly from the inside, and from a
manufactured ‘outside’ in which others like-us become objects-to-us.
Pierre Hadot distinguishes between the world of science and the world of
everyday perception. He regards the world of science as unrepresentable, constructed
by scientists. He says:
As we shall see, this does not mean that we are limited by our everyday perceptions/
conceptions of the world. Epiphany, transformation are always possible. That is per-
haps one of the great gifts diversely offered to us by Sigmund Freud, Carl Jung, and
their teachers and peers.What that means is that consciousness (and, indeed, uncon-
sciousness as a mode of existential experience) is central to all of this. Without
responsiveness, without awareness and its development, we do not exist as self-
reflexive creatures. Merleau-Ponty’s idea that consciousness is a project of the world
is spot-on, but the origin of consciousness and the world, how they come to be
in the first place, is unknown and probably unknowable. What we do know, now,
however, is that human beings are not the only living beings who are conscious.
Christof Koch’s discussion of his relationship with his dog is a beautiful and illu-
minating illustration of this (Koch, 2019).
At its basis, the idea that we represent the world to ourselves arises because of our
failure to acknowledge the interconnectedness of humans and Nature, even with
say, a Buddhist mindfulness orientation (Thompson, 2010;Varela et al., 2016). So by
way of contrast, I want to note that for some Buddhists, consciousness and suffering
are intertwined. On the whole, Buddhists attempt to explain the cause of suffering
and argue that it is because we have the mistaken notion of a self, yes, connected to
consciousness, that we suffer. It is important for them, therefore, to show that the
cause actually does not exist: if there is no self, there will be no suffering. But this
is something that we have to learn by un-learning what might be thought of as
our ontological commitment to self. In this view, one realises that one experiences
nothing but experience(s): consciousness if ‘emptied’ of self. There is no self that
experiences, there is simply conscious awareness, and constant change. In effect,
this is to attribute moral and psychological dispositions to an error of judgement,
and that error is that we are ignorant in believing in an ontologically grounded
reality. Perhaps what is needed is an idea of self that does not rely on the idea of
xiv Living Bodies and Consciousness
an unchanging substance, but, instead, incorporates change and fluidity. This would
agree with the changeableness we all experience in our lives. However, it would
not address the central role of conscious awareness and memory with which most
of us identify.
Khenpo Tsultrim Gyamtso Rinpoche remarks that
In my view, the idea of self does not precede the idea of other, if that is what is
meant by ‘from the idea of ‘self ’ comes that of ‘other’. The connection is there, but
reversed and is a given of phenomenology as we have just seen in Merleau-Ponty.
The interaction of self and other might be a cause of suffering, but that it is patho-
logical is not a given as Gyamtso’s claim suggests. Self and other interact in mul-
tiple ways, all of which do not result in suffering. Certainly if we grasp at things
or experiences or other persons, and are unsatisfied or disappointed in our efforts,
suffering will ensue. And cognition plays an important role in this, for knowledge
and ignorance, important cognitive elements are at the forefront to some kinds of
conscious awareness. And learning to deal with all of this helps with our capacity to
individuate, to become a self-reflecting conscious presence in the world.
mental objects, and it appears that such debates and controversies also have some
bearing on the relationship between psychoanalysis and phenomenology (Jacob,
2019; Siewert, 2017).
As Varela, Thompson and Rosch point out, representation has been a key theme
in cognitive science and computer modelling. But enactivist theorists rethink the
notion of intentionality away from representation and towards the mutuality, even
the reciprocity, of activity, of being in the world in the mode of Merleau-Ponty. For
them, cognition is ‘always about or directed toward something that is missing’, a next
step or a situation in the world (Varela et al., 1991: 205). And Varela,Thompson, and
Rosch explore cognition through cognitive science and its origins, and phenomen-
ology. They introduce the Buddhist practice of mindfulness as a possible avenue for
bringing together the whole of human experience in a way that is understandable
from scientific, phenomenological and personal, experiential perspectives.6
Specifically, the Buddhism to which they refer is Tibetan in the tradition of
Mahayana, the Buddhism of Gyamtso. They argue, using the Buddhist Aggregates
(forms; feelings/ sensations; perceptions (discernments)/ impulses; dispositional
formations; consciousness), that all ‘five together constitute the psychophysical
complex that makes up a person and that makes up each moment of experience’
(Varela et al., 2016: 64). They imagine what it would be to be in pursuit of the ‘real
self ’ which each of us takes ourselves to be. They conclude that the real self is not
in any one of the aggregates, nor is it in the sum of the aggregates, that ‘no such real
self is given to us in our experience’ (Varela et al., 2016: 69). After exploring and
rejecting alternatives from the Western tradition (Descartes’ res cogitans and Kant’s
transcendental ego) they conclude that the search for a real, substantial self will
always be frustrated. From the perspective of the present moment, we cannot dis-
cover a self that persists in our experience.
The trio identifies a circularity in thinking about cognition: ‘that our cognition
emerges from the background of a world that extends beyond us but that cannot
be found apart from our embodiment’. In their research, they argue that there is
no abiding self, no foundation, no objective ground that can be identified as an
unchanging, foundational self, always present in experience. The self is an illusion:
(w)hen we tried to find the objective ground that we thought must still be
present, we found a world enacted by our history of structural coupling …
organism and environment fold into one another in the fundamental circu-
larity that is life itself.
Varela et al., 1991: 217
How do they get to this position? In part, they accept the Buddhist idea of no-self.
In Buddhist traditions, meditation, sometimes characterised as mindfulness
(becoming aware that one’s mental life is composed of a succession of present
moments that slip away and can never be held) and Zazen bring about the realisa-
tion that change means that there is no substantial self. Buddhists argue either that
there is no substantial self or that they are agnostic about the self.7 It is the practice of
xvi Living Bodies and Consciousness
meditation that brings one to this conclusion. With practice, fully engaged medita-
tion is a non-narrative experience in which focus on the breath or bodily sensations
becomes a conscious, sensuous experience, unfettered by any assumptions or onto-
logical commitments. The silence and peacefulness that ensue bring relief from
suffering. In my view, the success of this practice is a cognitive insight: you have
to be able to do it though. Doing it, though, does not provide the grounds for the
ontological assumptions that Buddhists have developed out of meditation. Indeed,
the focus on one’s own consciousness foregoes the possibility of taking seriously
the claims of phenomenology, and of enactivism, and Buddhism. Hence I wonder
about the conclusion, an ontological claim, that the meditator reaches—that there
is no substantial self. That is, a basis of their claim, that experience of the ever-
changing mind/consciousness does not entail the conclusion that there is no self,
so something more is needed.
So although I have just said that mindfulness is unfettered by any assumptions
or ontological commitments, which amounts to a commitment to groundlessness,
viz. that everything is empty and constantly changing, there seems to me to be an
enthymeme operating here, that there is a ‘my’ to the awareness and experience
I take to be mine. Meditation on the succession of present moments, it is held,
shows that self is not substantial. However, the discovery of groundlessness or no-
mind is based on the practice of conscious, watchful awareness on the part of the
meditator. I wonder then, about the conception of no-self which is the result of the
practice: who or what is experiencing, and who or what is aware? I might say, for
instance, ‘So what? I know I am constantly changing, but it is the I (me) that knows
this that is in question, not what I know to be the case in my changing world, i.e.
that my self changes. What is the “I” that cognizes?’
Varela, Thompson, and Rosch imagine that a reader might pose a question
related to my concerns:
How is it, if we have no self, that there is a coherence in our lives? How is
it, if we have no self that, that we continue to think, feel, and act as though
we had a self –endlessly seeking to enhance and defend the non-definable,
non-experienced self?
Varela et al., 2016: 110
(i)n the case of all things which have several parts and in which the totality
is not, as it were, a mere heap, but the whole is something besides the parts,
there is a cause; for even in bodies contact is the cause of unity in some cases,
and in others viscosity or some other such quality.
Aristotle & McKeon, 1941: 1045a 8–12
If we think of the self as having several ‘parts’ (constituents, aspects) and the self
as a totality, which is not a mere heap, but something besides the parts (a reflexive
awareness for example) which is not merely the ‘circular structure of habitual
patterns’ and that the whole (the parts and the something besides) has a cause, then
we might be able to come up with a working notion of self that does not depend
on the notion of self as persistent, unchanging substance. We might, for example,
argue that self is indeed caused by the world in which we live, together with the
(reflexive) workings of consciousness, itself a property of the world, in this case, of
human beings in the world; and human beings are bodies. Thus consciousness is a
property of bodies and self is its reflexive awareness. This is a view in which the
causal nexus is viewed as the phenomenological coexistence of consciousness and
other, in which ‘I’ and ‘self ’ are experiential ‘parts’. And it is paradoxical, yes.
newgenprepdf
Hence we could discern here, a primitive notion of the self as both an effect of
cause(s) and a constituted entity beyond what constitutes it (that’s the paradox). We
acknowledge the phenomenological nature of self and other, and at the same time
preserve the ontological integrity of other. There is a strong, ontological sense in
which the world, in other words, is (not can be) separate from phenomenological
consciousness (the world pre-exists any consciousness as it will post-exist it), while
at the same time, self is both epistemologically and phenomenologically dependent.
This is the sense in which the world and consciousness are intertwined. One’s being
as a self is phenomenological being. This enlightened view is an aspect of individu-
ation. I shall have more to say about this in the following chapters.We can retain the
idea that self is enacted, but that enactment is phenomenological, and self requires
the ontological, participatory, integrity of the world.
Lastly, I maintain that there are two moments of consciousness: pre-narrative and
narrative consciousness, about which I also shall have more to say in later chapters.
A basic division, then, exists between unconscious, primitive experience and self-
conscious, aware, experience. The importance of these assumptions about bodies
and consciousness will become clear as I discuss what I think of as psychological
epiphany, Nature, Beauty, and Art and their dependence on the idea of change. The
link to individuation, to the deep awareness of self as reflective consciousness, vital
and ever changing but nonetheless persistently aware, will become clear, I hope.
Notes
1
Functionalism is the doctrine that what makes something a thought, desire, pain (or
any other type of mental state) depends not on its internal constitution, but solely on
its function, or the role it plays, in the cognitive system of which it is a part. More pre-
cisely, functionalist theories take the identity of a mental state to be determined by its
causal relations to sensory stimulations, other mental states, and behavior.
Levin, 2018
2 This is a small sample of what is available in the research.
3 When I use the term ‘individuation’ I am using it in a Jungian sense as I have in my pre-
vious books.
4 See Atamian et al. (2016).
5 See Kant (1998: passim) and Brook and Wuerth (2020). Note that there is much written
on this topic.
6 A new edition of which was published in 2017 with a Foreword by Jon Kabat-Zinn, a
master of mindfulness teaching. Francisco Varela died in 2001; the new Introductions are
by the surviving co-authors.
7 See, for example, Progressive Stages of Meditation on Emptiness in which Rinpoche argues
that ‘the self is simply a vague and convenient concept that we project now here and now
there on to a stream of experiences, and is nothing in or of itself ’ (Gyamtso, 1986/1988/
1994: 31).
INTRODUCTION
Herein lay the spring of the mechanical art and mystery of educating the
reason without stooping to the cultivation of the sentiments and affections.
Never wonder. By means of addition, subtraction, multiplication, and div-
ision, settle everything somehow, and never wonder.
Charles Dickens Hard Times 691
I hope this book brings you to Nature, Beauty, and Art through phenomen-
ology,2 and psychology and then on to Ethics and the Moral Life as practice and
transformation.
In Cartesian Philosophy and the Flesh, I worked with Pierre Hadot’s idea that phil-
osophy is practice. Hadot developed his thesis from his intensive study of ancient
DOI: 10.4324/9780429022975-1