Critical Thinking About Truth in Teaching
Critical Thinking About Truth in Teaching
Eko Ariwidodo
Introduction
“Teaching is not the lever for changing or
transforming society.
Formal education…cannot really be
the lever for the transformation of society.”
(P. Freire, 1987)
Truth in teaching, however, may very well have been the most
controversial issue in educational philosophy ever since Socrates
confronted the Sophists in ancient Greece. Deepened by Plato to the
issue of the role of knowledge in education, this question of truth in
teaching concerns the nature of knowledge and how it can promote the
good life for the individual and society. What is good knowledge?
What is knowledge good for?
Critical Thinking About Truth in Teaching
issues but only those aspects that can be dealt with objectively, e.g.,
when students learn information about drugs or sex but do not examine
related questions of value and morality. At the third level, ‘both sides’
of the issue are presented impartially and without comment to enable
students to learn about the different views on the issue. On the fourth
level, the teacher points out the advantages and disadvantages of each
view in turn. These higher levels would do a great deal to promote
critical thinking about the issues discussed.
A fifth level is attained when the teacher makes an internal
criticism of each view and abstracts its partial truth. For example, the
controversy between conservative and progressive educational
philosophies in the West started with Plato’s attempt to have the most
intellectually able students acquire the best knowledge available in
society through his invention of higher education. By the time he
retired from his Academy, its curriculum included the empirical
disciplines that Aristotle said belonged in education, e.g., biology,
chemistry, and medicine, with the focus upon their conceptual aspects
as outlined in the third level of Plato’s ‘divided line’. These are still
emphasized today in what are called academic subjects in honor of
Plato’s Academy. The half-truth that education involves building the
curriculum from the top down, however, was strongly controverted by
progressives such as Rousseau, Froebel, Pestalozzi, Francis Parker, and
John Dewey, who correctly insisted that genuine education depends
upon building the curriculum from the bottom up, i.e., on the child’s
actual development, by starting each lesson with the child’s own.
Thus the greatest conservative and progressive educational theories
ever written each has an extremely important truth: maintain the best
knowledge in society by having elite students acquire it at the
university, but always base one’s pedagogy and curriculum on the
present state of the pupils’ growth. On the one hand, no advanced
industrial society is going to abandon the academic tracks in secondary
schools that prepare students for the university (and other modes of
tertiary schooling), although Plato’s rationalistic epistemology is highly
of disputation, and that the school room is neither the tribunal to adjudicate nor the
forum to discuss it.”
4
Plato, Protagoras and Meno, trans. W. K. C. Guthrie (Baltimore: Penguin, 1956),
and Plato, The Republic, trans., D. Lee (Baltimore: Penguin, 1974). Originally
written circa 375 B.C.E., Book VI. 509d-511e.
5
John Dewey, Democracy and Education: An Introduction to the Philosophy of
Education (New York: Macmillan, 1916).
6
Martin Buber, Education, and, The Education of Character, trans. R. G. Smith, in
“Between Man and Man “ (New York, Macmillan, 1965), p. 83-117, Originally
published 1926 and 1939.
7
Paolo Freire, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, trans. M. B. Ramos (New York: Herder
& Herder, 1970).
8
D. Vandenberg, Education as a Human Right: A Theory of Curriculum and
Pedagogy (New York: Teachers College Press, 1990), or in : D. Vandenberg,
Education in Existential Perspective: The Dialectic of Education for Democracy, in
P. Higgs (ed.) Metatheories in Educational Theory and Practice (Johannesburg:
Heinemann, 1998), p. 141-165.
9
Morowitz, H., Hazen, R., & Trefil, J., Intelligent Design Has No Place in the
Science Curriculum, The Chronicle of Higher Education (September 2, 2005), p. 6-8.
10
Do neurologists explain away the truth of their own empirical research by referring
to their own brain processes as causing it? Of course not. As the director of
neurosurgery at John Hopkins Children’s Center, in: Ben Carson , Your Mind Can
Map your Destiny Ledger-Enquirer (Columbus, GA), in Parade section, 2003, p. 30.
He says : “The human brain, as I came to realize, is simply a mechanical component
of an entity of far greater beauty and power: the mind.” This attests to a person’s self-
conscious, free initiative, but it is not meant to deny the embodiment of the living
stream of wakeful consciousness.
11
Please check in : P. Freire, P, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, trans. M. B. Ramos
(New York: Herder & Herder, 1970), p.21-23; and see : P. Freire, & Shor, I., A
Pedagogy for Liberation: Dialogues on Transforming Education (South Hadley MA:
Bergin & Garvey, 1987), p.11-20.
12
I.Gur-Ze’ev, Adorno and Horkheimer: Diasporic Philosophy, Negative Theology,
and Counter-education, Educational Theory 55, 2005, p. 343, 344-345, 352, 356,
365.
13
J.F. Lyotard, Heidegger and the ‘Jews’, trans. A. Michel & M. S. Roberts
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1990), p.34, 38.
14
M. Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and other Writings, (ed.) C.
Gordon (New York: Pantheon, 1980), p.193.
15
H.S. Broudy, Building a Philosophy of Education, Englewood Cliffs, (NJ: Prentice-
Hall, 1961), p. 323, 339-340.
the natural, societal, and lived worlds, respectively, and they truthfully
disclose them to students16. As Charles Sanders Peirce claimed, the real
is that which is discovered by communities of qualified investigators
when the investigation is carried sufficiently far 17. Referring to it as a
minimal realism allows for subsequent investigations by qualified
investigators, paradigm shifts, etc.
Teachers who majored at the university in the subject they teach in
high school often understand the various kinds of empirical, rational,
quantitative, qualitative, historical, or interpretive methods and canons
of inquiry used in their area of expertise in domain-specific ways
relative to the characteristics of the things or phenomena in the domain.
As Alfred Schütz claimed, each discipline is a distinct province of
meaning with its own cognitive style and epistemic protocols18. Thus
the importance of perception, conception, experimentation,
quantitative, qualitative, historical, or interpretive research19 can vary
by the domain to promote truth in teaching. A meta-narrative of
knowledge that fits all domains is not needed to establish truth in
teaching within a specific domain20.
A second way to maintain the epistemic ethos of truth in teaching
and learning is to accept a loose, flexible combination of the main
theories of knowledge that retains the half-truth of each. Kant, for
example, roused from his dogmatic, rationalistic slumber by David
Hume, claimed that concepts without perceptions are empty, just as
16
D. Vandenberg, Knowledge and Schooling, Phenomenology & Pedagogy, 6, 1988,
p. 63, 70, 74.
17
C.S. Peirce, How to Make Our Ideas Clear, in Values in a World of Chance (ed.) P.
P. Wiener, (New York: Doubleday, 1958), p. 133-134. Or read : D. Vandenberg,
Education as a Human Right: A Theory of Curriculum and Pedagogy, (New York:
Teachers College Press, 1990), p.130-132, 218-220.
18
D. Vandenberg, Phenomenological Research in the Study of Education, in D.
Vandenberg (ed.) Phenomenology and Educational Discourse (Johannesburg:
Heinemann, 1997), p. 9, 11,12.
19
It may be worth noting that this paper engages in interpretive research understood
as a hermeneutic of exemplary texts to bring historically significant understandings to
bear on a contemporary problem.
20
D. Vandenberg, Charlatans, Knowledge, Curriculum, and Phenomenological
Research, in Philosophy of Education (Normal: Illinois State University Press, 1983),
p. 201-211.
21
M. Greene, Teacher as Stranger: Educational Philosophy for the Modern Age
(Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1973).
22
M. Merleau-Ponty, M.,The Phenomenology of Perception, trans. C. Smith (London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1962), and M. Merleau-Ponty, The Primacy of Perception
(ed.) J. Edie, Evanston, (IL: Northwestern University Press, 1964).
The small child has its being in the world perceptually such that it
comes to live in the primary world of the senses, which becomes
structured by nonverbal activities and the informal language of the
family. This tacit knowing, to borrow a phrase from Michael Polanyi23
(1964), who seems to strongly parallel Merleau-Ponty, persists
independently of school learning, sometimes in opposition to it, unless
a pedagogy brings these pre-judgments of things, these prejudices, up
into explicit awareness by the students’ exploration of their inner
horizons. When the interior exploration leads to the exploration of the
outer horizons in the world through curriculum content, it allows the
child or youth to pursue truth as well as its own being in the world by
letting things in the world be disclosed by the knowledge in the
curriculum--with the teacher’s guidance, of course. After indicating
how the child lives in the primary world of perception that will inform
the rest of its life unless revised through education, Greene suggests:
The crucial concern is for self-awareness and critical cognitive
action for the sake of gaining perspective on personal life and
remaking the social domain. How should the teacher determine
whether this should be his [sic] focal concern? How might the
differences among the philosophical points of view affect his
[sic] practical judgment? Can he [sic] not function on some
occasions as a latter-day rationalist and, on other occasions, as an
empiricist? Can he [sic] not, while functioning as a pragmatist,
pay sufficient heed to the truth of a student’s being to integrate a
notion of liberation with the Deweyan conception of what is
most worthwhile? 24
This perspective is postmodern, for it does not exalt one of the
theories of knowledge as if it were the only valid meta-narrative, but it
does not throw out the baby with the bath water by dismissing them
completely. It is neo-modern because it functions as did the aggregate
of Plato, Dewey, Buber and Freire mentioned earlier in this paper--on
the sixth level of neutrality. It retains the partial truths, i.e., the
23
M. Polanyi, Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy (New York:
Harper & Row, 1964).
24
M. Greene, Teacher as Stranger: Educational Philosophy for the Modern Age,
(Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1973), p. 168.
25
John Dewey, Democracy and Education: An Introduction to the Philosophy of
Education (New York: Macmillan, 1916), p. 201-203.
26
Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. J. Macquarrie & E. Robertson (New
York: Harper & Row, 1962), p. 145, 197, 334, and see : D. Vandenberg,
Phenomenology and Fundamental Educational Theory, in A. T. Tymieniecka (ed.)
Phenomenology World Wide (Lancaster, UK: Kluwer, 2003), p. 589-601.
27
Martin Heidegger, On the Essence of Truth, trans. J. Sullis, in Martin Heidegger:
Basic Writings (ed.) D. F. Krell (New York: Harper & Row, 1977), p. 113-141.
Conclusion
Truth in teaching therefore requires that the teacher be neutral in
regard to the controversies regarding various epistemologies, as Greene
recommends. This includes being neutral toward any model of critical
thinking that isolates thinking from a domain and from a domain-
specific epistemic ethos, for truth in teaching requires the flexible,
domain-specific epistemic ethos in the classroom. What is knowledge
good for? It opens one to the world as it opens the world to one. It lets
the being of the world and the being of the students come into being.
At least good knowledge, truth, enables one’s being in the world as it
enables the being of the world. Truth lets the Earth be four and a half
billion years old because it lets it be what it is29 Dis-closing the world
in its beauty and goodness, truth lets being be. Wa Allâh a’lam bi al-
shawâb.*
28
For example, ‘Water freezes at 32 degrees’ and ‘Water freezes at 0 degrees’ are
both true not because they correspond to reality but when and only when they disclose
some possibilities in the world to someone. Either can help one adjust a refrigerator’s
thermostat.
29
E. Jones (ed.), The Atlas of World Geography (London: Octopus, 1977), p. 22. And
see : G.S. Soreghan, Lessons From Earth’s Deep Time, The Chronicle of Higher Education,
July 15, 2005, p. B10.