The document discusses the importance of deliberate practice in achieving expert performance, highlighting that elite performers accumulate significantly more practice hours than their peers. It also contrasts the behavioral theories of Hull and Tolman, with Hull focusing on stimulus-response connections and Tolman advocating for a cognitive approach that includes mental processes like expectations. Tolman's research on latent learning and cognitive maps illustrates that learning can occur without immediate performance evidence, emphasizing the distinction between learning and performance.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes)
2 views8 pages
Learning Kitap - Kopya (5)
The document discusses the importance of deliberate practice in achieving expert performance, highlighting that elite performers accumulate significantly more practice hours than their peers. It also contrasts the behavioral theories of Hull and Tolman, with Hull focusing on stimulus-response connections and Tolman advocating for a cognitive approach that includes mental processes like expectations. Tolman's research on latent learning and cognitive maps illustrates that learning can occur without immediate performance evidence, emphasizing the distinction between learning and performance.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 8
For example, Ericsson et al.
(1993) compared student
violinists who were the “best” with those who were merely “good” and with those who were in training to become music teachers. The best students had accumulated about 7,400 hours of deliberate practice by the age of 18 compared to 5,300 hours for the good students and 3,400 hours for the teachers- in-training. Such differences account for why elite performers so often report having begun their training at an early age. An early start allows one to begin accumulating the huge number of practice hours needed to outperform others. Those who begin at a later age are simply unable to catch up. Because deliberate practice is so effortful, the amount that can be tolerated each day is necessarily limited. For this reason, elite performers often practice about 4 hours per day. Ericsson et al. (1993), for example, found that the best violin students engaged in solitary practice (which was judged to be the most important type of practice) for approximately 3.5 hours per day, spread out across two to three sessions, each session lasting an average of 80 minutes. Note that this did not include time spent receiving instruction, giving performances, or playing for enjoyment. The students also devoted about 3.5 hours a day to rest and recreation and obtained more than average amounts of sleep. Top-level performers in intellectual pursuits display similar characteristics. Novelists typically write for about 3 to 4 hours each day, usually in the morning. Eminent scientists likewise write for a few hours each morning—the writing of articles arguably being the most important activity determining their success—and then devote the rest of the day to other duties. Skinner is especially instructive in this regard. In his later life, he would rise at midnight and write for 1 hour, then rise again at 5:00 A.M. and write for another 2 hours. The remainder of the morning was devoted to correspondence and other professional tasks, while much of the afternoon was devoted to recreational activities such as tinkering in his workshop and listening to music. He deliberately resisted any urge to engage in serious writing at other times of the day, feeling that this often resulted in poor- quality writing the next morning. The limited amount of writing he did each day was more than compensated for by the consistency with which he wrote, resulting in a steady stream of infl uential articles and books throughout his career (Bjork, 1993). Skinner (1987) recommended that students adopt a similar approach to improve the quality of their writing. Congruent with this, research has shown that effective college students are more likely to describe themselves as utilizing a balanced approach to studying, involving regular study sessions with frequent breaks, than a driven approach, involving minimal breaks and studying to the point of exhaustion (Bouvier & Powell, 2008). Of course, Ericsson et al. (1993) do not completely discount the role of heredity in expert performance. Heredity might well affect the extent to which one becomes interested in an endeavor, as well as one’s ability to endure the years of hard work needed to become an elite performer. Nevertheless, the obvious importance of deliberate practice suggests that we should not be too quick to discount our ability to acquire a certain skill. Although many of us might not have the desire, time, or resources to become elite athletes, excellent musicians, or famous scientists, this does not rule out the possibility of becoming better tennis players, learning how to play the guitar, or signifi cantly improving our math skills. After all, the best evidence available suggests that it is largely a matter of practice. (See Ericsson, Charness, Feltovich, & Hoffman, 2006, for a recent comprehensive overview of scientifi c research on expert performance; see also Starkes & Ericsson, 2003, for an overview of research on expert performance in sports.)
What did concern him was whether the concept of hunger, as
defi ned in some measurable way (such as number of hours of food deprivation), was scientifi - cally useful and led to testable hypotheses. Hull’s theory was also a pure S–R theory because it assumed that learning consists of the establishment of connections between specifi c stimuli and specifi c responses. Thus, like Watson, he viewed behavior in a very mechanistic fashion. Lest this seem dehumanizing, recognize that it is not far removed from some modern-day cognitive approaches, which view humans as analogous to computers that process bits of information from the environment (input) to produce responses (output). This is actually quite similar to Hull’s model of behavior: Specifi c stimuli (input) yield specifi c responses (output), with certain internal events mediating the process. In fact, some versions of modern-day cognitive psychology can even be considered an outgrowth of Hull’s neobehaviorism.5 Hull was the most infl uential experimental psychologist of the 1940s and 1950s. Unfortunately, it turned out that major aspects of his theory (which are beyond the scope of this text) were very diffi cult to test. As well, the theory was highly mathematical and grew increasingly complex as equations were expanded and modifi ed. Many of these modifi cations were forced on Hull by his critics, the most famous of whom was Edward C. Tolman. (For a major overview of Hull’s theory, as well as to gain a sense of its complexity, see Hull, 1943.) FIGURE 1.2 In Hull’s neobehaviorism, theorists make use of intervening variables, in the form of hypothesized physiological processes, to help explain the relationship between the environment and behavior. Environmental events Internal events (intervening variables) Internal physiological processes, such as hunger and fatigue Observable behavior 5 Interestingly, people seem less critical of the cognitive information-processing approach to psychology, which draws an analogy between humans and computers, than they are of the traditional behavioral approach, which draws an analogy between humans and animals such as rats. Perhaps this is because we are impressed by the ability of computers to perform certain human-like tasks (e.g., play chess), and we are insulted by the notion that humans and rats have anything in common. Yet, outside their specialized abilities, computers are quite inferior to rats. Imagine, for example, that a man, a rat, and a computer are washed up on a deserted island. To the extent that the man emulates the rat (if he is capable of it), he will likely survive; to the extent that he emulates the computer, he will sit on the beach and rot. Rats have a marvelous ability to learn and adapt; present-day computers do not. Fortunately for us, humans are far more rat-like than computer-like.
Hull’s S-R theory of learning is often categorized as a
“molecular” theory because it viewed behavior as consisting of a long chain of specifi c responses connected to specifi c stimuli. Edward Tolman (1886–1959) disagreed with this approach and believed that it would be more useful to analyze behavior on a “molar” (i.e., broader) level. For example, he felt that we can understand a rat’s behavior in a maze more accurately as a goal-directed attempt to obtain food than as a long chain of discrete stimulus-response connections that, in machine-like fashion, lead to food (e.g., Tolman, 1932). This molar approach to learning is similar to the gestalt approach to perception (Kohler, 1947), from which Tolman drew much of his inspiration. To the gestalt psychologists, perception is not simply the summation of different bits of conscious experience but is instead a “holistic” process resulting in an organized, coherent, perceptual experience. We perceive a house as more than just a combination of bricks and boards; it is bricks and boards plus something more. As the famous gestalt saying goes, “the whole is more than the sum of the parts.” Similarly, for Tolman, behavior was more than just a chain of discrete responses attached to discrete stimuli. It was instead an overall pattern of behavior directed toward particular outcomes, and it can be properly analyzed only on that level. Although Tolman disagreed with much of Hull’s theorizing, he did agree that intervening variables may be useful in a theory of learning (in fact, it was Tolman who fi rst suggested this). However, while Hull’s intervening variables were physiological-type processes like hunger and fatigue, Tolman’s were considerably more mentalistic. The Tolmanian rat, as well as the Tolmanian person, was not simply motivated by drives and habits but also had “expectations” and “hypotheses.” Thus, Tolman’s cognitive behaviorism (sometimes called “purposive behaviorism”) utilizes intervening variables, usually in the form of hypothesized cognitive processes, to help explain behavior (see Figure 1.3). Tolman’s (1948) most famous intervening variable is the cognitive map, which is a mental representation of one’s spatial surroundings. Evidence for this concept was derived from a study on “latent learning” by Tolman and Honzik (1930). This experiment was conducted in an attempt to disprove Hull’s notion that behavior must be rewarded for learning to take place; that is, in the absence of some type of reward, nothing can be learned. To test this notion, Tolman and Honzik trained three groups of rats on a complex maze task (see Figure 1.4). The rats in a continuous-reward group always found food when they reached the goal box, but the rats in the two other groups found no food when they reached the goal box (they were simply removedfrom the maze and then fed several hours later). Training proceeded at the rate of one trial per day for 10 consecutive days. As expected, the rewarded group learned to run quickly to the goal box, whereas the two nonrewarded groups took much longer to do so. Following this initial phase of training, on day 11 of the study the rats in one of the nonrewarded groups also began receiving food when they reached the goal box. According to Hull, the rats in that group should only then have started to learn their way through the maze, which would have been demonstrated by a gradual improvement in their performance. What Tolman and Honzik found instead was a dramatic improvement in the rats’ performance on the very next trial. In fact, on day 12 of the study, the newly rewarded group slightly outperformed the group that had been receiving a reward from the outset (see Figure 1.5). Tolman interpreted these results as indicating that the initially nonrewarded rats had in fact learned the maze during the fi rst 10 trials of the experiment, and that they had learned it at least as well as the group that had been receiving food. He would later interpret these fi ndings as indicating the development of a “cognitive map” (Tolman, 1948), which only became apparent when the rats fi nally began to receive food. Thus, this experiment is regarded as a classic demonstration of latent learning, in which learning occurs despite the absence of any observable demonstration of learning and only becomes apparent under a different set of conditions. The experiment also demonstrates the distinction between learning and performance, because learning was apparently taking place even when the subjects showed no evidence of such learning in their performance at that time. (See, however, Jensen, 2006, for a more detailed exposition and critique of these fi ndings and how they have been interpreted.) Although Tolman believed that it was theoretically useful to incorporate cognitive variables, he remained, in many other ways, a standard behaviorist. For example, like Hull and Watson, he believed that introspective reports of thoughts and feelings are so unreliable as to be of little scientifi c value. He maintained that his own theoretical inferences about cognitive processes were based entirely on direct observations of behavior and were thus objectively based. Tolman once even apologized for the “shameful necessity” of having to discuss conscious experience in a text he was writing (Tolman, 1932)—a refl ection perhaps of how frustrated psychologists had been by the old introspectionist approach. Like other behaviorists, Tolman also believed strongly in the usefulness of animal research for discovering basic processes of learning, and almost all of his research was conducted with rats. Much of Tolman’s research was directly aimed at refuting Hull’s theory of learning. Hull was able, in increasingly complex ways, to modify his theory suffi ciently to account for many of Tolman’s fi ndings.6 As a result, during Tolman’s life, his cognitive approach never achieved the same popularity as Hull’s neobehavioral approach. With the advent of the cognitive revolution in psychology, however, many of Tolman’s research methods and concepts have been adopted by modern researchers. Cognitive behaviorism is now a fl ourishing fi eld of study, and the study of cognitive processes in nonhuman animals is specifi cally known as “animal cognition” or “comparative cognition.”