RWP11 001 Risse
RWP11 001 Risse
Mathias Risse
Harvard Kennedy School
January 2011
RWP11-001
www.hks.harvard.edu
Global Justice
Shylock makes his demand to a pound of his delinquent debtor’s flesh in terms of justice.
Until the clever Portia finds a device for voiding the contract, the presumption is that it
suspend. Kant goes too far insisting that there is no point for us to continue to live on
earth unless justice prevails. 2 Still, justice plays its central role in human affairs precisely
justice explains why certain individuals have particularly stringent claims to certain
certain people must be justifiable to them. Alongside distributive justice there is also
rectificatory justice, and perhaps other kinds. Yet since our concern in all but sections 8
and 9 is with distributive justice, “justice” means distributive justice unless otherwise
noted.
attention to the question of the conditions under which such stringent claims arise. Do
claims of justice arise only among those who share membership in a state? Alternatively,
do they arise among all those who are jointly subject to the global political and economic
order? Or do they apply among all human beings simply because they are human?
1
This piece was prepared for the Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy, edited by David Estlund. Many
thanks to Micha Glaeser, Gabriel Wollner, and David Estlund for helpful comments.
2
Kant (1996), p 473.
1
Inquiries into global justice differ from those into international justice precisely by not
limiting inquiry to what states should do. They may well also question the very moral
When Hobbes devoted De Cive to exploring the rights of the state and the duties
between individual and state, after all, meant not to focus on the relationship of the
relationship with an enduring institution that made exclusive claims to the exercise of
certain powers within a domain. Centuries later Kavka (1986) could write that “the
relationship between the individual and the State forms the core of Western political
philosophy,” just as “the relationship between morality and prudence lies at the center of
Western ethics” (p 21). Due to its focus on the state (a reflection of the political realities
of the age), until recently modern political philosophy has done comparatively little to
theorize justice outside of states, or to assess political and economic structures other than
Nowadays, however, we must ask with some urgency about the conditions under
which principles of justice apply. That inquiry is central to the burgeoning field of global
justice. This question about the applicability of principles of justice also generates
(renewed or new) interest in political structures such as a world state; a world with
federative structures stronger than the United Nations; with a more comprehensive
system of collective security; one where jurisdictions are disaggregated; or where border-
2
where enormous differences in life prospects nonetheless persist. Depending on what one
thinks about the conditions under which demands of justice apply, one may favor the one
or the other of these structures. Even if one thinks that subverting the state system is
practically impossible, one may still explore moral objections to it, specifically from a
standpoint of justice. Such inquiries naturally assume the shape of determining the
incorporates several premises. First, each individual has a good that deserves respect, and
individuals are due rights and protections to that end. Justice is not (merely) a matter of
realizing, say, a divine order. Second, some share of material goods is among the rights
and protections everyone deserves. Third, the fact that each person deserves such rights
and protections is rationally and secularly justifiable. Fourth, the distribution of these
enforce friendship. Fifth, it is for the state (and conceivably other political entities) to
achieve justice. These commitments about how the fates of individuals are tied are
that also generates the debate about global justice. If each individual has a good that
material goods are among the rights and protections everyone deserves, we must ask if
this depends on where people live. If protections require rational justification, we must
ask if such justification is available for (what below I will call) the normative peculiarity
of the state. If the distribution of these goods is practical, we must note that nowadays a
3
network of organizations seeks to make this true globally. Plausibly, entities other than
Let me explain what I mean by the “global (political and economic) order” and
hence by an “increasingly interconnected world.” Our current global society has emerged
from developments that began in the 15th century through the spread of European control,
While this order has no government, it comprises treaty- and convention-based norms
regulating territorial sovereignty, security and trade, some property rights, human rights,
and the environment. Politically, the United Nations Charter codifies the most significant
rules governing this system. Economically, the Bretton Woods institutions (International
Monetary Fund, World Bank, later also the General Agreement on Trade and
Tariffs/World Trade Organization) form a network intended to prevent war and foster
worldwide betterment. Jointly with more powerful states, these institutions shape the
economic order.
The term “globalization” describes processes that erode the political and
economic importance of national boundaries and increasingly affect life chances through
the system of rules that is constitutive of the global order. “Globalization” is not new. It
traces back to the spread of European control, a process accompanied by the emergence
of a state system whose central features were reflected in the doctrine of “sovereignty.”
Political philosophers of the 17th and 18th century, such as Grotius, Locke, Hobbes,
Wolff, Vattel, and Kant, explored questions about that stage of globalization. They
developed the doctrine of sovereignty, explored under what conditions one could acquire
non-European territories, or what kind of ownership there could be of the seas. The
4
spread of European control was complete by the end of the 19th century. By that time,
political philosophers such as Tocqueville and Mill had been busy justifying why non-
Europeans should endure political dependence. A period of devising rules for the spread
After World War II “global governance” came into its own, in the form of the
globalization must worry about normative issues that such governance raises. Among
these issues is the question of whether principles of justice indeed apply only within
states. Perhaps such principles apply to the global order as such. Or, again, they might
apply independently of political and economic structures, and instead hold because of
common humanity and thus apply to all human beings. By “positions on global justice” I
mean views about the conditions under which principles of justice hold.
between relationism and non-relationism. That distinction captures some of the most
justice only hold among persons who stand in some essentially practice-mediated relation
to each other. “Non-relationists” think such principles may apply among those who stand
in no such relation.
The relation of “being within 100,000 km of each other” is not essentially practice-
mediated, nor is, more relevantly, that of “being a fellow-human.” I talk about
5
especially with this latter relation, which, however, are dispensable to understanding its
considerations that render demands of justice applicable among persons for whom these
conditions and considerations hold. I use the term “grounds” to remain neutral between
relationists and non-relationists and thus arrive at a rather abstract formulation in terms of
Relationists may hold a range of views about the nature of the relevant relation.
They may disagree about the scope of justice, the range of people in the justice
relationship. Globalists think the relevant relation holds among all human beings in virtue
of the existence of practices that relate all humans to each other within a single global
order. Internationalists think the relevant relation holds (only) among individuals who
shared membership in states that generates demands of justice. Globalists owe an account
of what it is about involvement with, or subjection to, the global order that generates
demands of justice. Those who accept duties of justice that hold (only) among people
who share a state endorse “the normative peculiarity of the state;” those who do not,
reject it. Internationalists endorse the normative peculiarity of the state. Globalists and
3
I disregard differences between citizenship and permanent residency and speak of shared membership.
6
relationists, globalists and non-relationists are united by rejecting the normative
including all of (and only) humanity. Yet non-relationists may determine the scope
differently. One could limit justice to a subset of humanity by insisting on the normative
importance of, say, sex or race. Or one may insist that justice must have all sentient
beings in its scope, at least higher animals and conceivably rational Martians. Yet the
former possibility is implausible, and the latter I set aside. Non-relationists owe an
principles of justice as regulating practices that some persons share with each other. This
implies two things. First of all, for relationists principles of justice apply only to those
who respectively share the practices. Relationists are motivated by the moral relevance of
practices in which certain individuals stand. Such practices may include not only those
which individuals chose to adopt, but also those of which they have never chosen to
4
Some of my terminology draws on Sangiovanni (2007). Yet my usage deviates from his. For instance,
globalism, on my account, is by definition a relationist view. “Internationalism” often refers to political
movements advocating greater cooperation among nations, which is not what is mean. Often “statism” is
used for what I mean by “internationalism”. I prefer “internationalism” because the term captures an
understanding of global justice as composed of multiple entities within which principles of justice hold
respectively. Whatever moral principles apply globally would then differ from principles of distributive
justice, and hold between (“inter”) these entities. There are, of course, only so many terms to go around in
this domain.
5
Globalists and internationalists disagree about both grounds and scope, but agree that grounds are
relational. Relationists may also agree about the scope while disagreeing about the grounds. Below we
encounter coercion-based and cooperation-based internationalists. Both think the people who respectively
stand in the justice relationship are those who share a state. They agree about the scope of justice while
disagreeing about the grounds in the sense that they disagree about what it is about shared citizenship that
generates demands of justice. Distinctive of a ground is the account of the conditions and considerations
that are norm-generating. The term “scope” does not do much independent work. “Not much:” It would be
inappropriate to stipulate that grounds always be specified so precisely that the scope is uniquely fixed. Yet
once the grounds are fixed, disagreement about the scope should be relatively minor, of the magnitude of a
dispute about who exactly counts as a citizen given that this matter is largely fixed through legal rules. I
define “globalism” as a view about grounds, not as one about the scope that is consistent with a non-
relationist ground.
7
partake. Second, relationists think of principles of justice as only regulating those
practices, rather than every aspect of the lives of those who share them.
3. To illustrate what is at stake, note that John Rawls is a relationist. He famously calls
justice “the first virtue of institutions, as truth is of systems of thought” and talks about
“justice in social cooperation” ((1999b), p 3). (See the article, “John Rawls” by Leif
Wenar in this volume.) Justice here is a characteristic of institutions, which are practices.
His principles regulate the practices constitutive of the basic structure of society (the way
in which the major social institutions fit together into one system, and how they assign
fundamental rights and duties and shape the division of advantages from cooperation).
“Distributive justice,” says Freeman (2007) by way of expounding this approach, “poses
the general problem of fairly designing the system of basic legal institutions and social
norms that make production, exchange, distribution, and consumption possible among
free and equal persons” (p 305f). Many aspects of advantage and its distribution are
natural facts. But “what is just and unjust,” says Rawls ((1999b), p 87), are not these
facts, but “the way that institutions deal with these facts.”
Relationists can recognize duties to those with whom they do not stand in the
justice relationship. Alas, those duties would either differ relevantly from duties of justice,
or else in some other way differ from those duties of justice that hold among individuals
who share the relevant relation. Nagel (2005) adopts the former approach, insisting that
justice only holds within states. Rawls (1999a) adopts the latter. He implicitly
acknowledges a distinction between duties of distributive justice that hold within states,
and other duties of justice that may hold otherwise. The duty of assistance to “burdened
8
societies” in Law of Peoples is not one of distributive justice ((1999a), p 106, pp 113-120;
see also Freeman (2007), chapter 9). Duties of distributive justice are duties with regard to
shares in a system of economic production and exchange, which Rawls thinks presuppose
a basic structure.
justice. Law of Peoples adds an approach to international justice, by way of sketching the
foreign policy of a society within which his domestic principles of justice apply.
domestic justice and works “outward” from there to the Law of Peoples, and “inward” to
local justice ((2001), p 11). These other subjects presuppose domestic justice. As
The principles that appropriately regulate social and political relations depend
upon the kinds of institutions or practices to be regulated, and these principles are
to be ‘constructed’ on the basis of ideas that are central to the functioning of those
institutions or practices and people’s awareness of them. (p 270)
intuitions that must be in reflective equilibrium to obtain a theory of justice concern the
practices and institutions in which we lead our lives. These convictions are less
Wenar (2006) offers a plausible reading of Rawls that responds to critics, like
Caney (2002), who think Law of Peoples is incoherent with Rawls’ earlier work.
Crucially, both in the domestic and in the global case Rawls draws on ideas implicit in
the public political culture. Rawls believes “that humans should be coerced only
according to a self-image that is acceptable to them,” which means that “[s]ince ‘global
9
citizens’ cannot be presumed to view themselves as free and equal individuals who
should relate fairly to each other across national boundaries, we cannot legitimately build
coercive social institutions that assume that they do” (Wenar, p 103). Wenar rightly uses
this observation to explain why Rawls did not advocate global egalitarian ideals of a sort
that Beitz (1999) and Pogge (1989) found a natural extension of his principles. Global
public political culture is of a different (much thinner) nature than that of a constitutional
democracy.
justice to properties of individuals that omit too much of moral importance (for practices
individuals have not selected), or over-emphasize some morally important aspects at the
expense of others (for practices in which individuals chose to participate). Parallel to what
I said about relationists, non-relationism implies two things. Non-relationists seek to avoid
Second, since non-relationists do not limit justice in this way, they will plausibly apply
life. (“Will plausibly:” recall that there is logical space for non-relationists to proceed
broadly understood. While for relationists individuals stand in the justice relationship if
they have special claims within particular practices, for non-relationists that relationship is
6
Miller (2007), p 32f, reminds us that “arbitrary” sometimes means “undeserved” and sometimes “should
make no difference.” Differences in needs are undeserved, but should make a difference. The manner in
which I have introduced non-relationism above seeks to characterize this position in a way that avoids
pitfalls from this ambiguity.
10
distinguished by the absence of special claims. 7
Note two things in addition. First, grounds differ from circumstances of justice.
“whenever persons put forward conflicting claims to the division of social advantages
under conditions of moderate scarcity” (p 110). Both circumstances and grounds tell us
specify those living conditions of human beings under which any principles of justice
apply in the first place. Unless we live under such circumstances, no principles of justice
apply to begin with. If we live under these circumstances, the grounds specify which
Three elements are shared by all cosmopolitan positions: First, individualism: the
ultimate unit of concern are human beings, or persons (…). Second, universality:
the status of ultimate unit of concern attaches to every living human being equally
– not merely to some sub-set, such as men, aristocrats, Aryans, whites, or Muslims.
Third, generality: this special status has global force. (p 89)
the moral equality of persons. Each of these positions has capacities to makes sense of
individualism, universality, and generality. A crucial issue for each of these positions is
how rich a notion of moral equality its advocates wish to endorse, and how the relevant
notion of moral equality relates to ideas of political equality and distributive equality. In
any event, one needs additional arguments to derive distributive equality of anything
7
Tan (2004) captures the non-relationist’s concern with arbitrariness: “At the foundational level of
deliberation about global justice, impartiality requires that we do not allow people’s nationality to influence
our views of what people’s baseline entitlements are. (…) A person’s nationality, a mere accident of birth,
cannot by itself be a reason for giving her greater consideration at the foundational level” (p 158; see also
pp 27f and 159f). See also Pogge (1989), p 247; Moellendorf (2002), pp 55f, p 79.
11
from ideas of moral or political equality. Internationalists deny a close link between
moral and political equality: all human beings are morally equal, but it is only in the
presence of certain practices (those of shared citizenship in a state) that ideas of political
equality even apply. Internationalists may or may not find inequality among individuals
But they do not find inequality among countries as such morally problematic. Globalists
and non-relationists may endorse a global maximin or sufficiency criterion, or yet other
criteria. A range of views on inequality is open to them, but none that depends on shared
membership in states.
We have learned the basic cosmopolitan lesson: moral equality is an essential part
of any credible theory of global justice. In the domain of distributive justice, the term
“cosmopolitan” has become the victim of its own success. Therefore we should conduct
the philosophical debate in the terms discussed in this chapter, rather than in a way that
plateau.” All plausible theories of domestic justice define “the social, economic and
political conditions under which the members of the community are treated as equals”
(Kymlicka (2002), p 4). Similarly, all plausible theories of global justice ascribe
5. Non-relationists insist that relations in which particular individuals stand with each
other cannot have the kind of moral importance that would imply that moral obligations
12
(or anyway, a broad range of obligations) only apply among those who do so. Caney
(2005) offers a version of this approach. He offers the following thought regarding the
relevance of economic interaction, and a similar thought would apply to all practices:
Consider a world with two separate systems of interaction that have no contact but
are aware of each other and suppose that one of them is prosperous whereas the
other is extremely impoverished. Compare, now, two individuals – one from the
prosperous system and the other from the impoverished system – who are identical
in their abilities and needs. The member of the prosperous system receives more.
But it is difficult to see why – concentrating on any possible and reasonable
criteria for entitlement – this is fair. Ex hypothesi, she is not more hard-working or
more gifted or more needy. In all respects they are identical (bar one, namely that
one is lucky to live in the prosperous society and one is not) and yet an
institutionalist approach confers on one more benefits. (p 110) 8
To develop his case, Caney’s strategy is to identify a moral argument of sorts, and then to
argue that that argument appeals to properties that everybody has. Limiting such
arguments to particular groups means to commit what Caney, following Black (1991),
calls the “fallacy of restricted universalism:” “A distributive theory, that ascribes rights
and claims on the basis of certain universal attributes of persons, cannot at the same time
restrict the grounds for those claims to a person’s membership or status within a given
society” (p 357). Attempts to derive principles of justice from universal attributes that
nevertheless are supposed to be limited to certain groups (e.g., compatriots) commit this
fallacy. Consider the way in which Caney applies this strategy to civil and political
liberties. He argues for the “scope1 claim:” “the standard justifications of rights to civil
and political liberties entail that there are human rights to these same civil and political
because the standard arguments for civil and political rights invoke a universalist
‘moral personality.’ That is, the relevant aspect of persons is the right to be
subject to principles to which they can reasonably consent (for contractarians), or
8
See also Moellendorff (2002), p 79, and Tan (2004), p 158.
13
their use of moral language (for Habermas), or their humanity and status as
persons (for deontologists), or their ability to lead a fulfilling life (for
perfectionists). As such, it would be incoherent to adopt any of these lines of
reasoning for a particular right and then ascribe that right only to other members
of one’s community. (p 77)
Arguments of this sort at the very least pose a challenge for relationists to explain just
what it is about their preferred relation that, in the case that interests us, generates
demands of justice that would only apply among those who share that relation. Without
further ado, let us see whether they succeed at this task and so can respond to non-
6. Internationalists and globalists disagree about what relation is relevant for the
claims of justice on nationally or globally shared practices, respectively, and thus to some
extent use similar arguments to defend their views. Defenses of relationism may enlist
two strategies.
The first strategy draws on the fact that it is (conceptually) difficult for us
successfully to press demands upon each other at all, especially the stringent demands of
justice. Relationists are well-equipped to deal with this difficulty. They can help
themselves to considerations that arise from within the practices they consider central to
the applicability of justice. They need not deny that there can be natural rights and duties
of justice at all. But arguments in their support can enlist only features of shared
arguments relationists offer) can enlist a larger set of considerations. They can use claims
about persons having undergone certain transactions under specific conditions (e.g.,
14
promises, contracts), or about them living in certain human-made arrangements that
could often assume different shapes, and that put demands on those involved in them.
something for the claimant. We need reasons why others ought to provide what is
significant. Non-relationists can most readily meet that challenge if they restrict
such as basic needs satisfaction. Relationists are better equipped to make such a case. In
particular, duties pertaining to relative, rather than absolute, economic status are (at the
very least) easier to establish, and are more demanding, if we can resort to shared
inequality, and hence to differences in relative economic status. Scanlon identifies five
reasons to pursue greater equality: (1) to relieve suffering or severe deprivation; (2) to
domination; (4) the preserve the equality of starting places which is required by
procedural fairness; and (5) procedural fairness sometimes supports a case for equality of
outcomes. (2) and (5) are the clearest expressions of egalitarianism. (4) is consistent with
considerable inequalities and so is only weakly egalitarian. (1) and (3) are not egalitarian
at all. Scanlon argues that Rawls uses (2) - (5), and perhaps (1) as well, to argue in
support of his principles of justice. So those principles are supported by reasons that are
Crucially, however, even the force of (3) and (4) depends on the practices (if any)
that the relevant individuals share. For instance, to explain what counts as unacceptable
15
forms of power it helps to explore how individuals respectively contribute to the
maintenance of an economic system, and hence also what the economic ties among them
are to begin with. Undoubtedly, some exercises of power are unacceptable regardless of
what relations individuals stand in. But the more ties there are among individuals, the
more possibilities there will be for them to contribute to the maintenance of relations,
which in turn generate rationales for them to complain about certain exercises of power.
Similarly, to assess how much reason there is to preserve the equality of starting places
procedures the individuals are jointly subject. Thus if we seek to argue for obligations
pertaining to relative standing without making use of relations, there is little we can say
in the first place. We can derive more demanding obligations if we can resort to relations.
account of the link between special relations and responsibilities. Relations create
have reasons to see oneself under, and actually have, special obligations. As Scheffler
puts it, to attach non-instrumental value to a relationship with somebody means “to be
disposed, in contexts which vary depending on the nature of the relationship, to see that
person’s needs, interests, and desires as, in themselves, providing me with presumptively
decisive reasons for action, reasons that I would not have had in the absence of the
relationship” (p 100). (To call reasons “presumptively decisive” means to grant that in
principle they could be outweighed although they present themselves as reasons upon
which agents must act.) Skepticism about such responsibilities succeeds only if we have
no reasons at all to value our relations non-instrumentally. The case is clearest for family
16
ties and friendships, but less clear for political relations, and presumably internationalists
can more readily make it than globalists. Beitz (1999), for instance, does not use such
reasoning to support his globalism but wonders instead about the relevance of such
the normative peculiarity of the state. They could first use the two strategies in support of
peculiarity of the state to rebut globalists (and thus settle the intramural debate between
relationists once relationism as such has been accepted). Two proposed accounts of the
normative peculiarity of the state are coercion-based internationalism (e.g., Blake (2001),
These views, however, face the challenge that forms of coercion and cooperation
also hold within the global order as such, which makes it problematic to argue that
principles of justice only govern the relation among those who share a state.
Internationalists can respond by arguing that the normative peculiarity of the state is
instance, accounts for the state’s coerciveness in terms of legal and political immediacy.
The legal aspect consists in the directness and pervasiveness of law enforcement. The
political aspect consists in the crucial importance of the environment provided by the
state for the realization of basic moral rights, capturing the profundity of this relationship.
But assuming that something like Risse’s (2006) account succeeds in explaining
17
what is morally special about shared membership in states, one must still wonder whether
this account matters for justice, that is, can explain why principles of justice apply only
among those who share a state. That is the point that globalists push. Capturing globalist
involves a pattern of transactions that produce substantial benefits and costs; their
increased volume and significance have led to the development of a global
regulative structure. (…) Taken together, these institutions and practices can be
considered as the constitutional structure of the world economy: their activities
have important distributional implications. (pp 148f)
It does not matter precisely what the nature of international economic interdependence is.
The dispute between internationalists and globalists already arises for a loose sense of
interconnectedness.
means taxing poor nations so that others may live in “just” regimes (p 149f). Beitz’ target
is Rawls. He argues that if Rawls’ case for his principles of justice succeeds their content
should not change as a result of enlarging the scope of the original position to include the
global order. Beitz considers two objections (pp 154-161). The first insists that
interdependence is necessary, but insufficient for the applicability of justice. The global
order lacks any effective decision making mechanisms, as well as any real sense of
community, and these, the objector says, are also necessary for an order’s being subject
to standards of justice. Beitz responds that these differences fail to show that principles of
justice do not apply globally. Instead, they show that it is harder to implement the
principles.
requirements of global principles even if justice applies globally. Rich countries may
18
deserve their advantages because of differences in organization, or technology. Beitz
responds that this means to base entitlements on morally arbitrary factors like those that,
as Rawls insisted, ought not to affect one’s share of social primary goods. Thus he rejects
this move much as Rawls rejects principles of justice drawing on undeserved social or
genetic characteristics.
7. One way of making progress in light of the debate among internationalists and
globalists that I have presented in section 6 is to deny that there is a single justice
relationship in which any two individuals either do or do not stand. One may use
“principles of justice” as a collective term for different principles with their respective
ground and scope. Let us call non-graded or monist internationalism the view that
principles of justice either do or do not apply, that they do apply within states, and thus
among people who share membership in a state, and only then. Non-graded or monist
internationalism allows for associations such as the WTO, the EU, or the global order as
such to be governed by principles of justice, but endorses the normative peculiarity of the
state. Among the principles that apply within other associations we find weakened
versions of principles that apply within states. For this reason I talk about graded
internationalism in this case. I am lacking the space to motivate the graded view in detail.
Suffice it to say that all those who live, say, under WTO are tied to each other much more
loosely than individuals who respectively share a state. It is therefore plausible to think
19
that the principles of justice that hold within the WTO are weakened versions of those that
However, now that we have introduced a non-monist view, we also must take
seriously the idea that some grounds could be relational, whereas others would not be.
We must consider the possibility that there is no deep conflict between relationism and
overall plausible theory that recognizes both relationist and non-relationist grounds.
Integrating relationist grounds into a theory of justice pays homage to the idea that
individuals find themselves in, or join, associations and that membership in some of them
generates duties. Integrating non-relationist grounds means taking seriously the idea that
some duties of justice do not depend on the existence of associations. One obvious non-
relational ground to add is common humanity. One view that develops these ideas could
be called pluralist internationalism. This view would endorse the normative peculiarity
of the state, but recognize multiple other grounds of justice, some of them relational (e.g.,
subjection to the global trade regime) and others not (e.g., common humanity).
grounds, all of which would be binding, say, for states and international organizations.
relationism.
This view offers one way of preserving the plausible aspects of non-relationism,
globalism, and internationalism. Needless to say, making this view credible, and proving
its fruitfulness, requires detailed discussions of its implications for a wide range of areas.
The theoretical costs of making such a move are considerable because one would give up
20
on the uniqueness of the justice relationship. One would also have to meet the challenge
that such a pluralist view does not, one way or another, collapse into one of the original
views. Other ways of making progress in this debate are possible as well, including those
that abandon the state’s normative peculiarity. We have now reached the research frontier
in this field. 9
8. So far we have only talked about distributive justice. However, perhaps the main
theme to explore in an assessment of global justice is whether the global order wrongfully
harms some people, presumably the weakest, the global poor. If so, we should think of
global justice primarily in terms of moral obligations to rectify harms (where the harms
are not simply defined by a conception of distributive justice). There are different ways
of articulating that thought. First, one may say the global order wrongfully harms human
beings because of the sheer existence of borders. Perhaps frontiers are inconsistent
especially with the value of freedom and with liberal justice. Second, perhaps the global
order wrongfully harms the poor (i.e., individuals who are unable to meet basic needs) by
alternatives. Finally, one may argue that the extents of poverty and inequality themselves
reveal that the global order wrongfully harms the poor. Let me elaborate.
One way of making the point that national borders can function as unjustified
9
I develop pluralist internationalism in my book The Grounds of Justice, to be published by Princeton
University Press.
10
See Sen (1985) and (1999) and Nussbaum (2006) and (2000).
21
life with dignity. “Bodily integrity” is on her list, of which one instantiation is “being
able to move freely from place to place” ((2006), p 76). The challenge is to explain why
this capability can be limited by frontiers. However, appeals to the value of freedom to
assess the legitimacy of borders cut both ways. It is true that frontiers limit choice, but so
does any immigration policy. Permissive immigration policies in countries where many
people wish to live are likely to constrain some who already live there.
Some have argued that immigration barriers are unjust owing to liberalism’s
commitment to moral equality. Liberalism, Carens (2003) notes, condemns the use of
morally arbitrary facts about persons to justify inequalities. Examples include race, sex,
and ethnicity. Political communities that treat people differently on the basis of such
features are illiberal and unjust. Yet citizenship seems as arbitrary as any of those.
injustice because it differentiates rights based on origin. Carens is correct that moral
equality and the value of common humanity cannot stop at borders, but it has been argued
that this does not mean shared citizenship is as morally irrelevant as race or ethnicity. The
fact that shared citizenship arises in a manner for which individuals deserve neither credit
nor blame does not make it morally irrelevant. On this view, there is no inference from
In a related vein one may argue that a system of states cannot properly consider
all affected interests and so they automatically wrongfully harm persons. The actions of
states affect many who have no say in the design of policies. For instance, Mexicans who
wish to enter the US never consented to there being an American people that can
11
For elaboration, see Blake (2001).
22
unilaterally constrain immigration. Yet interests can be properly considered in domain-
specific ways. To the extent that trade policies affect interests, for instance, we should
ensure that such policies are fair. But that does not mean one must enfranchise everybody
immigration policies that spell out how many people from country A have a claim to
immigration to B. But once these claims are met, no additional demands, especially to
Let us proceed to the argument that the global order harms the poor because there
is a feasible alternative under which situation of the global poor is improved, as presented
money. It would just take 1.2% of the income of rich economies, $312 billion annually,
to bridge the aggregate shortfall of those living on less than $1 per day to the $2 line (p
7). Pogge’s proposal for raising some of those funds is the Global Resource Dividend,
which taxes extraction of resources. Yet while Pogge’s calculations show that abject
doubtful whether financial transfers are enough to seriously mitigate poverty. Suppose in
situation S1 we have the funds to cover the financial shortfall. We still need reliable ways
of distributing funds to individuals who do not simply have bank accounts that they can
securely access. We would also need an environment where individuals can actually
spend the money on available goods and services. Both times this involves institutional
improvements, especially if one wants the changes to be lasting. Similar points apply if
one wishes to support medical and educational advancements. One cannot simply start to
“work on AIDS,” but must build and maintain medical infrastructure. One cannot
23
improve education by building a few school houses, but must invest in teacher training,
That sustainable measures for enduring changes require good institutions has
become a guiding insight for many at the intersection between the social sciences of
development and its practice. Having funds to close the aggregate financial shortfall
between S1 and S2 is at best necessary, but not sufficient for S2 to be feasible. Pogge
may respond that while it is true that money does not automatically educate or cure
anyone, the money would be used precisely to take care of these things in appropriate
ways. Money is not enough by itself, but the other necessary conditions normally require
money. This is fair enough, but the relevant points now are these. We have found a sense
in which the poor are wrongfully harmed, namely, if not enough effort goes into
exploring possibilities for implementing appropriate institutional change. But while this
proposal to ascertain how to go about creating a feasible alternative and who is guilty of
9. Let us consider the import of poverty and inequality statistics. Statistics do not show in
any obvious way that the global order harms (let alone wrongfully harm) the poor. For
instance, while indeed 1.2 billion people in 1998 lived below the poverty line of $1.08
PPP 1993 per day (Pogge (2002), p 98), 12 there is now less misery than ever before, as
measured in terms of any standard development indicator. The progress made over the
last 200 years is miraculous. In 1820, 75% of the world population lived on less than $1 a
12
PPP means Purchasing Power Parity: the poverty line is fixed at what $1.08 bought in the US in 1993.
24
day (appropriately adjusted). Today, in Europe, almost nobody does, in China less than
20% do, in South Asia around 40%, and altogether slightly more than 20% do. The share
of people living on less than $1 a day fell from 42% in 1950 to 17% in 1992. Historically
What conclusion such statistics warrant depends on (a) the period considered
(“Sub-Saharan Africa has made progress over a 200-year horizon, but not for the last 20
years”), (b) whether one looks at absolute or relative quantities (“the number of
abysmally poor has remained unchanged for 15 years, but their share of the world
population decreased”), and (c) whether one looks at individuals or countries (“the
median developing country has experienced zero growth over the last 20 years; still,
inequality between two randomly chosen individuals has fallen” – because of growth in
India and China). Still, what is remarkable is not that so many now live in poverty, but
that so many do not; not that so many die young, but that so many do not; not that so
many are illiterate, but that so many are literate. If one looks at the last 200, 100, or 50
years, things have improved dramatically for the poor. The 200-year and the 50-year
horizon (roughly speaking) are especially significant. The former captures the period
when the industrial revolution has perfected the system of the division of labour, which
what are nowadays industrialized countries but that have worked to everybody’s benefit.
The 50-year horizon captures the period when the global order has come into its own.
Historically speaking, the global order at least seems to have benefited the poor
dramatically.
25
Surely, one may say, developing countries are better off than 200 years ago, but
should we not assess if wrongful harm has occurred by asking what things would be like
had European supremacists never invaded the rest of the globe? The trouble is that it is
impossible to say anything about this benchmark. What are we to make of the idea that
the world would be a better place if states had never emerged, or if colonialism had never
happened? Such questions defy sensible answers. It is hard (if not impossible) to assess
when agents came close to deciding differently, or natural events may readily have
occurred in other ways. It is equally hard to assess what alternate course would then have
emerged. Had Europeans not colonized Africa, alternate political structures may have
civilizations. It is also conceivable that war would have thwarted such efforts. According
states.
There is yet another way of articulating the thought that developing countries are
being harmed by the global order: a benchmark of fairness, the reference point being a
state of nature where resources are distributed fairly. “’Worldwide 34,000 children under
age five die daily from hunger and preventable diseases.’ Try to conceive a state of nature
that can match this amazing feat of our globalized civilization!” writes Pogge (2004), p
274. Yet state-of-nature references cannot distinguish between the view that the global
order does harm, and any other view explaining how such poverty could arise. Such
references only show that things are not as we would have hoped. Whatever else is true,
among the three benchmarks we have considered, the historical benchmark is the only
26
one which we can make sense of. In terms of that benchmark, the global order has
10. There are many questions about global justice that I have been unable to discuss here.
The philosophical foundations of human rights have attracted much attention recently.
(See the article by Alan Buchanan in this volume.) Topics that are both in need of much
more, and accessible to, philosophical analysis include immigration and fairness in trade.
In need of but less accessible to philosophical analysis is the question of how to distribute
the burdens from climate change. Deserving of more attention are also political and
economic structures other than states. We must explore, for instance, what demands of
justice, but also what types of accountability, apply to entities like the World Trade
One topic whose more systematic resurrection political philosophy would benefit
tremendously from is humanity’s collective ownership of the earth. (See Peter Vallentyne
on “Left Libertarianism” in this volume for more on this subject.) To illustrate, suppose
the population of the US shrinks to two, but they control access through border-
surveillance mechanisms. Nothing changes elsewhere. Surely these two should permit
immigration since they are grossly under-using their area. We can best explain this view
by the fact that all of humanity has claims to the earth. Immigration is but one topic
which such theorizing could illuminate. Humanity’s ownership of the earth was the
pivotal theme of 17th century political philosophy. In an age in which global problems
have become central, we have much to gain from reinvigorating that standpoint.
27
Literature
Caney, Simon. 2005. Justice Beyond Borders: A Global Political Theory. Oxford:
Carens, Joseph. 2003. “Who Should Get In? The Ethics of Immigration
Freeman, Samuel. 2007. Justice and the Social Contract. Essays on Rawlsian
University Press.
605.
28
Kavka, Gregory. 1986. Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory. Princeton:
Miller, David. 2007. National Responsibility and Global Justice. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Nagel, Thomas. 2005. “The Problem of Global Justice.” Philosophy and Public
Pogge, Thomas. 2004. “’Assisting’ the Global Poor.” In Deen K. Chatterjee (ed.),
The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Pogge, Thomas. 2002. World Poverty and Human Rights. Cambridge: Polity.
122.
29
Rawls, John. 1999a. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
University Press.
Risse, Mathias. 2006. “What to Say about the State.” Social Theory and Practice
32 (4): 671-698.
and D. Reidy (eds.), Rawls’ Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia? Oxford: Blackwell.
Williams, Bernard. 2005. In the Beginning was the Deed. Realism and Moralism
30