Is The Market A Test of Truth and Beauty Essays in Political Economy Yeager Download
Is The Market A Test of Truth and Beauty Essays in Political Economy Yeager Download
https://ebookbell.com/product/is-the-market-a-test-of-truth-and-
beauty-essays-in-political-economy-yeager-5272366
https://ebookbell.com/product/our-stock-is-rising-an-elementary-
students-introduction-to-the-stock-market-gregory-a-powell-55229612
Where Credit Is Due Bringing Equity To Credit And Housing After The
Market Meltdown Christy Rogers John A Powell
https://ebookbell.com/product/where-credit-is-due-bringing-equity-to-
credit-and-housing-after-the-market-meltdown-christy-rogers-john-a-
powell-28536990
https://ebookbell.com/product/is-there-a-doctor-in-the-house-market-
signals-and-tomorrows-supply-of-doctors-richard-m-scheffler-51942496
https://ebookbell.com/product/the-making-of-the-german-postwar-
economy-political-communication-and-public-reception-of-the-social-
market-christian-l-glossner-2570634
Redefining The Poverty Debate Why A War On Markets Is No Substitute
For A War On Poverty 1st Edition Kristian Niemietz
https://ebookbell.com/product/redefining-the-poverty-debate-why-a-war-
on-markets-is-no-substitute-for-a-war-on-poverty-1st-edition-kristian-
niemietz-34004298
https://ebookbell.com/product/the-end-of-globalization-why-global-
strategy-is-a-myth-how-to-profit-from-the-realities-or-regional-
markets-alan-m-rugman-57345124
Is The East Still Red Socialism And The Market In China Gary Blank
https://ebookbell.com/product/is-the-east-still-red-socialism-and-the-
market-in-china-gary-blank-37501314
https://ebookbell.com/product/economic-policy-in-the-digital-age-how-
technology-is-challenging-the-principles-of-the-market-economy-jrg-j-
dtsch-57157264
The Market Is Always Right The 10 Principles Of Trading Any Market 1st
Edition Thomas Mccafferty
https://ebookbell.com/product/the-market-is-always-right-
the-10-principles-of-trading-any-market-1st-edition-thomas-
mccafferty-1398374
Is the Market a Test of
Truth and Beauty?
Is the Market a Test
of
TRUTH BEAUTY?
Essays in Political Economy
by
L B. Y
:
Contents
Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . vii
:
Should Austrians Scorn General Equilibrium eory? . . . .
Why Subjectivism? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Henry George and Austrian Economics . . . . . . . . . . .
e Debate about the Efficiency of a Socialist Economy . . .
e Debate over Calculation and Knowledge . . . . . . . . .
Austrian Economics, Neoclassicism, and the Market Test . . .
Is the Market a Test of Truth and Beauty? . . . . . . . . . .
Macroeconomics and Coordination . . . . . . . . . . . . .
e Keynesian Heritage in Economics . . . . . . . . . . . .
Hutt and Keynes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
e Image of the Gold Standard . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Land, Money, and Capital Formation . . . . . . . . . . . .
Tacit Preachments are the Worst Kind . . . . . . . . . . . .
Tautologies in Economics and the Natural Sciences . . . . . .
:
Free Will and Ethics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Elementos del Economia Politic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Is ere a Bias Toward Overregulation? . . . . . . . . . . .
Economics and Principles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
American Democracy Diagnosed . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Civic Religion Reasserted . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
A Libertarian Case for Monarchy . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
vi
Contents
Index . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Introduction
is book’s title is the same as the newly chosen title of chapter , “Is
the Market a Test of Truth and Beauty?” at chapter, along with the
one before it, questions a dangerously false argument for the free-market
economy sometimes made by its supposed friends. eir argument threat-
ens to discredit, by association, the powerful and valid case for the mar-
ket. Asked whether the market is a test of truth and beauty—of excel-
lence—Ayn Rand would presumably give the same answer as mine: “No,
of course not!” Consider her hero of e Fountainhead, Howard Roark.
Political economy is the area of overlap among economics, political
Thscience, and philosophy. Beyond its positive content, political economy
does bear on policy but not only on policy; it is far from a hodge-podge of
different people’s policy prejudices. Economics, when not disregarded, is Th
obviously relevant to policy. So are philosophy and psychology, as when
they underlie doctrines such as redistributionism and egalitarianism. Pol-
icy can affect economics. More exactly, a policy proposal may help clar-
ify a strand of economic analysis even when, considering side-effects, the
author does not actually recommend the policy; “Land, Money, and Cap-
ital Formation,” chapter , provides an example. Regrettably, though,
policy-driven economists do exist who start with their or their employ-
ers’ preferred policies and then twist their analysis into supporting them.
Writings in political economy, being interdisciplinary, typically omit
the deep technicalities of any specific field. Most of this book’s chapters
are semipopular pieces that the attentive “general reader” should under-
stand. ey deal with intersecting fields rather than with advanced details
of any one field. Left out of this book, then, are any of my relatively tech-
nical writings, as on monetary theory and international economics. A few
semitechnical chapters, including numbers and , come close to mak-
ing an exception. Chapter contributes to a field of particular interest
to Austrian economists, capital theory. Yet it too strives for nontechnical
language.
viii
Introduction
2000
Acknowledgments
appeared, and chapter (also renamed) has been modified at its beginning
to read less like an invited introduction to others’ articles. Several pages of
chapter have been cut out because they rebut a strained interpretation of
Mises’s work that is hardly worth attention. Chapter , “ e Debate about
the Efficiency of a Socialist Economy,” although and perhaps especially
because it dates from , is printed unchanged.
e selection process has just happened to give the book an Austrian
flavor not originally intended. e bulk of my work is not particularly
Austrian. On whether I count as an Austrian economist, see the opening
lines of chapter .
1949
Introduction
Part : Economics
1995
Some strands of GE do perhaps deserve scorn 317
or neglect. But let us
keep our scorn well focused. e problem lies not with the theory’s
6 I
Part : Economics
central ideas but with some abuses committed in its name. ese include
parades of sham rigor and mathematical games that make no contact
with reality (cf. Buchanan / , Allais ). More specifically, they
arguably include obsession with the mathematical requirements for exis-
1983 out1988
tence, uniqueness, and stability of GE to the extent of crowding atten-
tion to economic substance. (On the other hand, let the would-be mathe-
maticians amuse themselves as they like, provided they not deceive other
people about the significance of their efforts.) A related abuse is pushing
the strongest-link principle, the tacit idea that a theory is as strong not as
its weakest but as its logically most rigorous link (cf. Mayer , pp. x,
– , , – , and passim). Still others are frontiersmanship and other
varieties of tacit methodological preaching (cf. chapter below).
e correct response to abuses is to pinpoint them. If we appraise a
doctrine or approach or technique by whether or not it might be abused,
misinterpreted, distorted, set aside, or taught with unduly narrow and
exclusive emphasis, we are putting it to a test that no doctrine can pass.
GE is often charged with being static and being preoccupied with
an all-around equilibrium in which all plans mesh and all prices, being
at their market-clearing levels, convey exact information. e services of
the mysterious auctioneer leave no scope for entrepreneurial activity and
57 actual
other 63 market
80 127
processes.130 e theory ignores complexity, uncertainty,
judgment, creativity, and enterprise.
Part : Economics
Part : Economics
Part : Economics
1932 1967 IV
14 I
Part : Economics
equations reveal the true nature of pricing, and the pricing process can-
not be accurately presented in any simpler form. e demand for a prod-
uct represents an attempt to attract certain factors of production to a
particular use. Conflicting with this attempt are similar attempts in the
form of demands for other products. ere arises in this way a strug-
gle for the relatively scarce factors of production, which is decided in
the exchange economy by placing uniform prices on the factors, which
prices in turn determine the prices of the products and thus form a
means of effecting the necessary restriction of demand. e demand for
a particular factor of production arising from the continuous demand for
each particular product is totalled for each unit period, to form a total
demand for that factor of production, ... which must, in a state of equi-
librium, equal the given quantity of the factor of production. ( / ,
p. )
its critics quite sure that their acquaintance with GE does not help make
those points seem obvious? Would they have grasped their full significance
even without contemplating the equation systems?
Only rather simple mathematics is required for reaping the benefits
claimed for GE. (Understanding work like Gerard Debreu’s is another
matter.) is brings up a related point. Quite a few Austrians maintain
that mathematics is out of place in economics. But how can they be confi-
dent? eir not seeing how to do anything useful with it is no reason
to suppose that no one else can use it any better. People with different
personal abilities, backgrounds, and tastes legitimately pursue different
research topics and employ different methods and styles of exposition. An
approach lacking appeal to oneself may convey valuable insights to other
persons. It is paradoxical for Austrians, especially those who like to expa-
tiate on subjectivity and ineffability and the unpredictability of the future,
to predict the usefulness of particular methods and to try practically to
legislate on such matters.
Alain Enthoven, then applying economics in the Defense Depart-
ment, testified to how overlearning or overstudy, as one might call it, can
help clinch one’s grasp of economic reality. e analytical tools that he
and his colleagues used
Part : Economics
GE is a major strand of, approach to, and integrating factor of the whole
body of economic theory. A single correct body of theory is what all cre-
ative economists presumably strive for, even though probably no one ever
will achieve it complete and error-free. Reality is consistent with itself,
and so must the correct theory of it be. To say so is not to deny the value
1950 27
of different schools with their own favorite topics, approaches, research
methods, and styles of exposition. A researcher can gain encouragement
and stimulus from knowing that he has colleagues out there who are ready
to read him sympathetically. ey accord him a presumption—defeasible
of course—that he is right. us, there is legitimate scope for the Austrian
School, as for others.
But the Austrians should think of themselves as making their own
distinctive contributions, critical as well as positive, to an emerging single
correct body of theory. eir objective should not be to differentiate them-
selves from the mainstream in a hostile manner but rather to contribute to
the mainstream and help steer it in the right direction. Correct economic
theory does not come in distinct and incompatible brands, one for Aus-
trians, one for Marxians, one for conservatives in the style of William F.
Buckley and Russell Kirk, one for libertarians, one for left-liberals, and
so forth. To suppose that it does is what Ludwig von Mises ( / ,
chap. ) eloquently condemned as “polylogism.”
Archibald, G.C., and R.G. Lipsey. “Monetary and Value eory: A Critique of
Lange and Patinkin.” Review of Economic Studies ( ): – .
Arrow, Kenneth J., and Frank H. Hahn. General Competitive Analysis. San Fran-
cisco: Holden-Day, .
1
. “Political Economy: – .” Lecture of April . In Ideas, eir
Origins, and eir Consequences, edited by omas Jefferson Center Founda-
tion, – . Washington, D.C.: American Enterprise Institute, .
14
1986
18 I
Part : Economics
Lucas, Robert E., Jr., and omas J. Sargent. “After Keynesian Macroeco-
nomics.” In After the Phillips Curve: Persistence of High Inflation and High
Unemployment, – . Boston: Federal Reserve Bank of Boston, 1963 .
Mayer, omas. Truth versus Precision in Economics. Aldershot, U.K., and Brook-
field, Vt.: Elgar, .
Patinkin, Don. Money, Interest, and Prices. ⁿ ed. New York: Harper & Row,
.
Yeager, Leland B. “Tacit Preachments are the Worst Kind.” Journal of Economic
Methodology ( ): – . Reprinted here as chapter .
1949 3
1966
1965
[Scale=1.0775]black2
Why Subjectivism?*
Part : Economics
74 76
22 I
Part : Economics
Such measures and proposals underrate the value of freedom and flex-
ibility. Arbitrary measures burden some people lightly and others heav-
ily because different people’s lives afford different scopes of substituting
away from the restricted consumption and make advance scheduling of
activities difficult and unrestricted flexibility important in widely differ-
ing degrees. In unrestricted voluntary transactions, by contrast, people
can allow for such differences.
A narrowly technological outlook is often linked with puritanical mor-
alizing. (I remember my maternal grandmother, who used to bewail the
waste of using a teabag only once if it could be made to serve twice and
of using and washing a large plate if the food could be crammed onto a
small plate.) Recovery techniques left too much oil and gas in the ground,
natural gas on the continental shelf was flared, and the prevailing practice
in coal mining left half of a seam in the ground merely because it was
needed there as a supporting column or because getting it all out was too
expensive—so went one complaint (Freeman , pp. – ). Energy
has been wasted by “too little” insulation of buildings.
Yet so-called waste was probably sensible at the lower energy prices of
the past. ere can be such a thing as too much conservation; for exam-
ple, producing aluminum for storm windows installed under tax incentives
even consumes energy in other directions. Ample heat and air condition-
ing brought comfort, and fast driving saved valuable time. Not having to
concentrate on ferreting out ways to conserve energy saved mental capac-
ity for other purposes. Now, at today’s higher prices, a dollar spent on
energy no longer buys as much comfort or saves as much time or thought
as before; and people respond accordingly. Conceivably, of course, the
energy prices of the past, distorted downward by interventions, may have
led people to consume more energy than they would have done at free-
market prices; but if so, the specific distortions should have been identified
and addressed. Moralizing about ways of consuming less was off the track.
Such moralizing almost regards waste as something perpetrated only
with material resources, not with people’s time or comfort or peace of
mind. Ironically, this strand of materialism sometimes occurs among peo-
ple who announce Galbraithian scorn for the alleged materialism of the
affluent society. Another apparent strand sometimes found in the attitude
of such people is self-congratulation on heroic hard-headedness in recog-
nizing necessary austerities. (Speaking at a conference in Beverly Hills on
April , Senator Gaylord Nelson welcomed the challenge of helping
to create the new and simpler lifestyles of the future.)
24 I
Part : Economics
1968
Chapter : Why Subjectivism?
Part : Economics
1960
Chapter : Why Subjectivism?
Part : Economics
ese kinds include what F.A. Hayek ( ) called “knowledge of the par- 1945
ticular circumstances of time and place,” knowledge that could hardly be
codified in textbooks or assembled for the use of central planners, knowl-
edge that can be used, if at all, only by numerous individual “men on the
spot.” It includes knowledge about all sorts of details of running business
firms, including knowledge of fleeting local conditions. It includes what
people know about their own tastes and particular circumstances as con-
sumers, workers, savers, and investors. Subjectivist economists recognize
how such factors not only underlie the prices that consumers are prepared
to pay for goods but also underlie costs of production.
Each consumer decides how much of each particular good to buy
in view of the price of the good itself, the prices of other goods, his
income and wealth, and his own needs and preferences. Subject to qualifi-
cations about how possible and how worthwhile precise calculation seems,
he leaves no opportunity unexploited to increase his total satisfaction by
diverting a dollar from one purchase to another. Under competition, the
price of each good tends to express the total of the prices of the addi-
tional inputs necessary to supply an additional unit of that good. ese
resource prices tend, in turn, to measure the values of other marginal out-
puts sacrificed by diversion of resources away from their production. Prices
therefore tell the consumer how much worth of other production must be
forgone to supply him with each particular good. e money values of for-
gone alternative production tend, in turn, to reflect consumer satisfactions
expectedly obtainable from that forgone production. (I say “reflect”—take
account of—in order not to claim anything about actual measurement of
what is inherently unmeasurable. I speak only of tendencies, furthermore,
for markets never fully reach competitive general equilibrium.)
With prices bringing to their attention the terms of choice posed by
the objective realities of production possibilities and the subjective reali-
ties of other persons’ preferences, consumers choose the patterns of pro-
duction and resource use that they prefer. eir bidding tends to keep any
unit of a resource from going to meet a less intense willingness to pay for
its productive contribution (and thus the denial of a more intense willing-
ness). Ideally—in competitive equilibrium, and subject to qualifications
still to be mentioned—no opportunity remains unexploited to increase
the total value of things produced by transferring a unit of any resource
from one use to another. Changes in technology and consumer prefer-
ences always keep creating such opportunities afresh, but the profit motive
keeps prodding businessmen to ferret them out and exploit them.
Chapter : Why Subjectivism?
Part : Economics
Part : Economics
advantages and hunches about fruitfulness and not let himself be badgered
into foretelling the unforetellable.
James Buchanan achieved one of the greatest triumphs of subjectivism
in demonstrating ( / ) that the burden of government spending
can indeed be largely shifted onto future generations by deficit financ-
ing through issue of bonds. e conventional wisdom among economists
(shared even by Ludwig von Mises, 1958 though not1999
by the general public)
had been unduly materialistic: the burden cannot be shifted through time,
since resources are used when they are used. Buchanan recognized that a
burden is something subjectively perceived. Persons who voluntarily give
up current command over resources in exchange for government bonds
that they find attractive suffer no burden in doing so. It is in the future
that people—in general, people other than the original bond-buyers—will
bear the burden of paying taxes to service the debt or of losing through
its inflationary or outright repudiation. Furthermore, bond-financed gov-
ernment deficits do affect allocation of resources in time by trenching
on private capital formation, thereby worsening future economic oppor-
tunities.
Part : Economics
Part : Economics
Part : Economics
“ ”
On a few points, some Austrian economists may not have been subjec-
tivist enough. Murray Rothbard ( , pp. – ) seems to think that a
contract under which no property has yet changed hands—for example,
an exchange of promises between a movie actor and a studio—is somehow
less properly enforceable than a contract1970under which some 77 payment
81 has
already been made. Blackmail is a less actionable offense than extortion
through application or threat of physical force ( , p. n. ). If a
villain compels me to sell him my property at a mere token price under
threat of ruining my reputation and my business by spreading vicious but
plausible lies, his action is somehow less of a crime or tort than if he had
instead threatened to kick me in the shins or trample one of my tomato
plants (Rothbard , esp. pp. – , – , and personal correspon-
dence). e material element in a transaction or a threat supposedly makes
a great difference.
I may be at fault in not grasping the distinctions made in these
examples, but it would be helpful to have further explanation of what
superficially seems like an untypical lapse from subjectivism into materi-
alism.
Far more common is the lapse into overstating the subjectivist posi-
tion so badly as to risk discrediting it. F.A. Hayek is not himself to blame,
but a remark of his ( , p. ) has been quoted ad nauseam (for example 1962
Chapter : Why Subjectivism?
Language: English
BY
THE REV. DR. BREWER,
TRINITY HALL, CAMBRIDGE,
HEAD MASTER OF KING’S COLLEGE SCHOOL,
NORWICH,
IN UNION WITH KING’S COLLEGE, LONDON.
LONDON:
JARROLD AND SONS, 47, ST. PAUL’S CHURCHYARD,
ALSO HAMILTON AND CO., SIMPKIN AND CO.,
AND WHITTAKER AND CO.
PREFACE.
Of all science, none is more generally interesting than that which
explains the common phenomena of life. We see that salt and snow
are both white, a rose red, leaves green, and the violet a deep
purple; but how few persons ever ask the reason why! We know that
a flute produces a musical sound, and a cracked bell a discordant
one—that fire is hot, ice cold, and a candle luminous—that water
boils when subjected to heat, and freezes from cold; but when a
child looks up into our face and asks us “why,”—how many times is it
silenced with a frown, or called “very foolish for asking such silly
questions!” The object of the present book is to explain about 2000
of these “silly questions” (which are often more easily asked than
answered) in language so simple that a child may understand it, yet
not so childish as to offend the scientific; and in order that the
answers may be strictly correct, not only the most approved modern
authors have been consulted, but the manuscript has been
submitted sheet by sheet to the revision of two gentlemen of
acknowledged reputation for scientific attainments. To the Rev. A.
Bath Power, M. A. especially, great obligation is due, for a careful
revision of the whole manuscript, for many excellent hints, and
useful additions. In conclusion, so much diligence has been
bestowed upon this little work for nearly ten years, so much useful
information has been supplied by scientific friends, and so minute a
revision has been made of every answer, that it is no presumption to
express a hope that this “Guide to the Scientific Knowledge of
Things Familiar” will become generally useful and acceptable, not
only to the young, but to those advanced to maturer life.
In this work some questions occur more than once, because they
serve to illustrate different principles; and whenever cognate
questions occur, the answers have been rendered as similar as
possible, in order to assist the memory of the learner.
SUBJECTS OF THE CHAPTERS.
PART I.—HEAT.
PAGE
I. The Sun a source of heat 2
II. Electricity a source of heat 3
3-
Thunder and lightning
29
III. Chemical action a source of heat 30
III.—Combustion 36
IV.—Smoke and smoky chimneys 59
V.—Lamps and candles 74
VI.—Animal heat 83
VII. Mechanical action a source of heat 95
VII.—Percussion 95
VIII.—Friction 98
VIII.—Compression 102
IX. Effects of heat 103
X.—Expansion 103
XI.—Liquefaction 126
XI.—Vaporization (clouds) 127
XII.—Evaporation 156
XIII. Communication of heat 164
XIII.—Conduction 164
XIV.—Absorption 184
XV.—Reflection 192
XVI.—Radiation (dew) 195
XVII.—Convection (boiling) 231
PART II.—AIR.
XVIII. Air 240
Rust 257
Tarnish 259
XIX. Carbonic acid gas 264
Froth. Effervescence. Fermentation, &c. 269
XX. Carburetted hydrogen gas 279
Fire damp 280
Safety lamp 281
XXI. Phosphuretted hydrogen gas 283
Ignis fatuus 285
Ghosts 286
XXII. Wind 287
XXIII. Barometer 317
Ten special Rules 319
XXIV. Snow. Hail. Rain 331
XXV. Water 342
XXVI. Ice 349
Frost 357
Freezing mixtures 360
XXVII. Light 363
Reflection. Telescopes. Refraction 386
Spectacles 389
Rainbows 394
Colour 399
XXVIII. Sound 409
Ear trumpets 415
Echoes 416
XXIX. Miscellaneous 419
Attraction. Anti-putrescents. Sleep.
424
Dreams.
Glossary 426
Index 427
PART I.
HEAT.
INTRODUCTION.
Q. What is heat?
A. The sensation of warmth.
Q. What is lightning?
Q. Why does the resistance of the air make the lightning zig-
zag?
A. As the lightning condenses the air, in the immediate advance
of its path; it keeps flying from side to side, in order to pass
where there is the least resistance.
ebookbell.com