L02 Preferences and Utility 2014
L02 Preferences and Utility 2014
A
y1
y2
x1 x2 X
Varian’s Version
• Let bundle X = (x1, x2) and Y = (y1, y2) where the
goods are x1 and x2 .
So the goods listed on
X2 the axes and the
quantities of each good
in the first bundle are
X the using the same
x2 notation.
y2
x1 y1 X1
Varian’s Version
• He does this to be consistent with his
advanced micro text.
good 2 In that text, he uses vector
notation and eliminates the
subscripts by not noting
quantities of each good on
X
the axes.
good 1
Modeling Preferences
• IMO, students have invested so much math time with X and Y on the axes,
dy
that I want to leverage that. E.g. slope = dx
• Also, with all the derivations coming up, we will have plenty of subscripts
floating around that I hate to add an additional set with goods X1 and X2.
A
y1
y2
x1 x2 X
Modeling Preferences
• Three choices: A B, consumer strictly prefers bundle A to bundle B
A B, consumer weakly prefers bundle A to bundle B
A B, consumer indifferent between bundle A and bundle B
Y
• And therefore
If A B, and B A then A B
A If A B, and not A B then A B
y1
y2
x1 x2 X
Axioms of Preference
• Axiom: a proposition that is assumed without proof for
the sake of studying the consequences that follow from
it (dictionary.com).
– These are based on ensuring logical consistency.
• Completeness: A B, or B A, or both, meaning A B.
– Any pair of bundles can be compared and ordered
• Reflexivity: A A , or A A
– A bundle cannot be strictly preferred to an identical bundle.
• Transitivity Let C = (x ,y )
3 3
If A B, and B C then A C
– Not a logical imperative according to Varian, but preferences become intractable if
people cannot choose between three bundles because A B, and B C and C A
• Continuity, next page
Continuity
• Preferences must be continuous
Rules out this situation:
• The bundle with more X is always preferred. Holding
X constant, more Y is better.
Y • B A, C A
• But, no matter how close C gets to A, C B
• The utility function in this case must be
discontinuous (i.e. there must be a vertical jump
Ub=15 B between A and C
Ua=10 Uc=20
A C
X
Goods, Bads and Neutral Goods
• Goods are good (more is better)
• Bads are bad, less is better
• Neutrals mean nothing to the consumer
• Some goods start out good, but then become
bads if you consume too much
Possible Indifference Mappings Thus Far
Characterize the Goods
Y Y Y
X X X
Y Y Y
X X X
And we have…
Both are good
but become bad Y is a neutral good Two goods
Y Y Y
X X X
X good and Y bad
Y Y Y
Two bads
X good that
becomes
bad, Y good
X X X
Perfect Compliments and Substitutes
Perfect Compliments: Perfect Substitutes: Two
More is only better if goods, indifferent to
you have more of the trading off a constant
Y other Y
amount of Y for X
X X
Well-behaved Preferences
• If we want to avoid situations where demand
curves are upward sloping or people spend all
their money on one good, then we need well-
behaved indifference curves.
• Preferences must also be
– Monotonic
– Convex
Monotonic
• Monotonic: If bundle A is identical to B, except
A has more of at lease one good, then A B
– A.K.A, nonsatiation or “more-is-better”
– Ceteris paribus, increasing the quantity of one
good creates a bundle that is strictly preferred.
– Indifference curves must be downward sloping.
– Paired with transitivity, means indifference curves
cannot cross.
Monotonic
• These still possible
Y Y
Y
X X X
Indifference Curves Cannot Cross
A C, share an indifference curve
B C, share an indifference curve
A B, transitivity
Y A But A B, monotonicity
X
Convexity
• Convexity: People prefer more balanced
bundles.
– Let A = (x1, y1) and B = (x2, y2).
– Define C = (tx1 + (1-t)x2, ty1 + (1-t)y2)
• where 0 ≤ t ≤ 1
– then C A and C B
Y
A
y1
C
t y1 + (1-t)y2
B
y2
x1 tx1 + (1-t)x2 x2
X
Convexity:
Indifference Curves Bound Convex Sets
• Convexity: Bundles weakly preferred to those lying
on an indifference curve bound a convex set.
– Any bundle which is a weighted average of bundles on the
indifference curve are weakly preferred to bundles lying on
the curve.
Y Y
A
y1
A
y1
B
B
y2
y2
x1 x2
X x1 x2
X
Convex Preferences
• These still possible
Y Y
X X
Strict Convexity
Indifference Curves Bound Convex Sets
• Strictly Convex Preferences:
– Any bundle which is a weighted average of bundles on the
indifference curve are strictly preferred to bundles lying on
the curve (weights 0 > t > 1).
C A, C B
Y
A
y1
C
ty1 + (1-t)y2
B
y2
x1 tx1 + (1-t)x2 x2
X
U=4
X
Convexity: Intuition
• Which implies indifference curves bow towards the
origin.
U=4
Y
U=7
U=10
U=7
U=4
X
Marginal Rate of Substitution
• The change in the consumption of the good on
the Y axis necessary to maintain utility if the
consumer increases consumption of the good on
the X axis by one unit.
• MRS = the slope of the indifference curve.
dy
• Although, dx
0 , MRS is almost always defined as
the abs value of the slope.
• In this class, MRS dy
dx
MRS = MB
• The MRS describes, at any given point along
the indifference curve, the consumer’s
willingness to give up Y for one more X.
• It is therefore the marginal willingness to pay
for X
• I.e. it is the marginal benefit of consuming X.
Digression: Cardinal Utility
• Utilitarians believed that utility, like temperature or height, was
something that was measurable (Cardinal utility).
– And that a unit of utility was the same for everyone so if we could find out
how to measure it, we could redistribute to maximize social welfare.
– The hope of some way of measuring utils did not survive long.
• Early neoclassical economists (e.g. Marshall) still held the idea
that for an individual, utility may be a cardinal measure.
– Believed marginal utility was strictly decreasing.
– Marshall’s demand curve was downward sloping for this reason.
– He is the reason P is on the vertical axis. Diminishing willingness to pay
reflected diminishing marginal utility.
• Also believed that utility was additive, consumption of one good
did not affect the MU from another (Uxy = 0).
Digression: Ordinal Utility
• Pareto (1906) first considered the idea that ordinal
utility (ordering the desirability of different choices)
might be the way to think of utility.
• Work by Edgeworth, Fischer and Slutsky advanced the
theory.
• Hicks and Allen (1934) came up with the defining
theory… that we still use today.
• Pareto, Vilfredo (1906). "Manuale di economia politics, con una
introduzione ulla scienza sociale". Societa Editrice Libraria.
• Viner, Jacob. (1925a). "The utility concept in value theory and its
critics". Journal of political economy Vol. 33, No. 4, pp. 369-387
• Hicks, John and Roy Allen. (1934). "A reconsideration of the theory of
value". Economica Vol. 1, No. 1, pp. 52-76
The Utility Function
• A utility function is simply a way to
mathematically represent preferences.
• Utility is Ordinal: The ability to order bundles
is all that matters.
– The magnitude of the difference in utility is
meaningless as the numbers reflecting utility are
arbitrary.
– No interpersonal comparisons are possible.
The Utility Function
• A function such that
A B if and only if U(A) U(B)
• Preference can be represented by a
continuous U=U(A) so long as preferences are
reflexive, complete, transitive, continuous
• Note, monotonacity and convexity are not
needed.
• Monotonacity is always assumed because it
makes the existence proof easier and more
intuitive.
The Utility Function
• While we need preferences to be reflexive,
complete, transitive, continuous for utility
functions to exist.
• We need monotonacity and convexity to make
them well behaved.
• By well behaved, we want unique solutions
that are not extreme and are relatively stable.
– We don’t want individuals spending all their
income on one good or slight changes in price or
income to drastically affect the optimal choice.
Revisiting Monotonacity
• As all indifference curves are strictly
downward sloping, they will all cross a 45 deg
line.
y d
x
Revisiting Monotonacity
• Monotonacity, Weak and Strong
– We will assume strong, so no thick indifference
curves!
Weak Monotonacity Strong Monotonacity
U(d) U(d)
d d
Establishing Monotonocity
• We need to demonstrate that the indifference
curve is downward sloping.
– Say U0 = U(x, y)
– Solve for y = Y(x, U0), making the implicit function,
U = U(x, y), explicit.
– Calculate dy/dx
Example
• Say we have U = x2*y
– Solve to get:
• y = U/x2
• dy/dx = -2U/x3
• Also, U = x2*y,
• So dy/dx = -2y/x
– For all U and all x > 0, dy/dx < 0 and nonsatiation
holds.
• However, it may not be possible to solve for Y
explicitly (e.g. U = 6y5 – 3xy + 7x3)
dy/dx via Implicit Differentiation
• We start with an implicit function (identity) defining an
indifference curve. To hold when x changes, y must
change too.
U 0 U x, y(x)
dU 0 dU x, y(x)
dx dx
dU 0 U x, y(x) dx U x, y(x) dy
dx x dx y dx
U x, y(x) U x, y(x) dy
0
x y dx
U x, y(x) dy U x, y(x)
y dx x
U x, y(x)
dy x U (x, y) U
x x
dx U x, y(x) U y (x, y) Uy
y
https://www.khanacademy.org/math/calculus/differential-calculus/implici
t_differentiation/v/implicit-differentiation-1
Example
• Start with U = x2*y
dy U
X
dx UY
– And
U X 2 xy
U y x2
dy 2 xy 2y
2
dx x x
U=U(x, y)
U
Y
This utility function
is strictly concave
as drawn
X
Indifference Curves are Level
Curves
• Level Curves
– Are a slice of the utility function at some U = U0
– Even if the utility function is not concave (as drawn
above), but only strictly quasi concave, these level curves
bound convex sets
– Convex sets and level curves
• Any line connecting two points on the same level curve lies
within the set
• So bundles with more balance than two bundles lying on an
indifference curve will provide more utility (the utility function
will be “above” any line connecting two points on an
indifference curve.
Convexity
• Convexity
– DOES NOT IN ANY WAY indicate that the utility
function is convex as opposed to concave.
– Convex functions and convex sets are two different
concepts.
• “Strictly”
– Strictly quasi–concave utility function means the
utility function has no flat spots and it’s level sets
are strictly convex
– Strictly convex level curves means the indifference
curves have no straight line segments
– “Strictly” required to ensure just one optimum
Convexity of Preferences Implies Indifference
Curves Bound Convex Sets
This will hold if the
utility function is
Strictly Quasi U=U(x, y)
Concave
Y
Utility Function
Not Concave, Any point on one of these
but Strictly Quasi dotted lines (exclusive
Concave as the level of end points), provides
sets bound convex more utility than the end
sets points
X
Convexity
• Convexity of preferences will hold if:
– dy/dx increases along all indifference curves (it
gets less negative, closer to zero)
– That is, either:
• The level sets are strictly convex
• The utility function is strictly quasi-concave
Convexity (level curves)
• dy/dx increases along all indifference curves
• We can use the explicit equation for an
indifference curve, y=Y(x, U0) and find
d2y
2
0
dx U U
0 to demonstrate convexity.
• That is, while negative, the slope is getting
larger as x increases (closer to zero).
Alternatively (level curves)
• As above, starting with U(x,y)=U0,
dy U ( x, y ) dy
MRS X , assuming MRS=
dx U Y ( x, y ) dx
• So convexity if
U X ( x, y )
d
2
d y U Y ( x, y )
2
0
dx dx
Convexity (level curves)
• And, that is
U X ( x, y )
d 2U U U U 2U U 2U
2
d y U ( x , y ) xy x y y xx x yy
2
Y
3
0
dx dx Uy
*Note that Uxx and Uyy need not be negative and Uy3>0
• What of:
– Ux > 0, monotonacity, nonsatiation
– Uy > 0, monotonacity, nonsatiation
– Uxx, ?
– Uyy, ?
– Uxy, ?
Diminishing MU vs
Diminishing MRS
• Both involve the idea of satiation. That is, the
more you consume, the less you value added
consumption.
• DMU: Consumption of other goods irrelevant
• DMRS: The value of consuming additional units
of one good along an indifference curve falls
because you are necessarily consuming less of
other goods.
Strict Quasi-Convexity (utility function)
• Convexity of preferences will hold if the utility
function is strictly quasi-concave
– A function is strictly quasi-concave if its bordered
Hessian 0 fx fy
H fx f xx f xy
fy f yx f yy
– is negative definite
0 fx fy
0 fx
H 0 and H f x f xx f xy 0
fx f xx
fy f yx f yy
Negative Definite (utility function)
• So the utility function is strictly quasi-concave if
– 1. –UxUx < 0
– 2. 2UxUyUxy-Uy2Uxx -Ux2Uyy > 0
• Related to the level curve result:
– Remembering that a convex level set comes from this
d 2 y (2U xU yU xy U y U xx U x U yy )
2 2
2
3
0
dx Uy
– We can see that strict convexity of the level set and strict quasi-concavity of
the function are related, and each is sufficient to demonstrate that both are
true.
With all Six Axioms/Assumptions
Y
A B C
U(A) U(B) U(C)
B U(A)
C
U(B)
U(C)
X
Some Utility Functions and their Properties
• Homotheticity of Preferences
• Elasticity of Substitution
• Functional Forms
– CES
– Cobb-Douglas
– Perfect Substitutes
– Perfect Compliments
Homothetic Preferences
• The MRS depends only on the ratio of goods
consumed.
• So any MRS that can be reduced so that x and y only
appear as the ratio (x/y) or (y/x) are considered
homothetic.
• Changes in income lead to equal percent changes in
consumption (income elasticity = 1 for all goods).
Elasticity of Substitution,
• What is the % change in the ratio of y*/x*
when there is a 1% change in MRSxy?
Y y*/x* = slope of
y*
(0,0) x* X
Elasticity of Substitution,
% (y * /x*)
%(MRS)
Change in y/x
Y all different
% change in MRS
from the slope of
the original tangent
line to each of
these is the same y*
x* X
Elasticity of Substitution,
• As an elasticity, it is true that
% (y * /x*) d(y * /x*) (MRS) d ln(y * /x*)
%(MRS) d(MRS) (y * /x*) d ln(MRS)
• U A n x
CES utility: n 1
N
where A > 0; n 0;
n 1
n 1; ρ<1; ρ 0; > 0
• And often to or or
1
U x y x y
U x y U
where A 1, =
where A 1, = 1 where A 1
0<ρ 1 = , 0, 1
0<ρ 1
CES, Constant Elasticity of Substitution
• Start with this form and find Ux:
1
U A x y where A > 0; ρ -1; ρ 0; =1
1
A 1
U x x y x 1
( 1)
U x x 1 A x y
A
Multiply by
A
1 ( 1)
A
U x x 1 x y
A
CES, Constant Elasticity of Substitution
• Transform the original utility function
1 1
U
1
Transform U: x y
A
1 1
U
x y
A
1 ( 1)
U A1
Substitute in to U x x 1 x
y
A A
Yielding
1
A1 U
U x x 1
A A
CES, Constant Elasticity of Substitution
• Simplify
1 1
A U
U x x 1
A A
And simplify
( 1) U 1
Ux x
A
U 1
Ux
A x ( 1)
1 1
U U
So, U x , and similarly, U
A x A y
y
CES: MRS and σ
• With Ux and Uy we can define MRS and σ:
Ux
MRS =
Uy
y * px
d *
x py
*
px y
d *
p x
y
CES: MRS
1
U
1
Ux A x y
MRS =
1
Uy U x
A y Homothetic!
CES: σ
y* px
d *
x py
px y*
d *
p x
y
1
y
*
px
Utility max requires x * and y* such that: *
x py
1
y * px 1
So, at U-max: *
x p y
CES: σ
• Split it up: y* px
d *
x py
1
y * px 1
* , and
x* p y
y* px
p y
d x *
p x
d * y
x py
px y*
d *
p x
y
Split this into two parts, first deal with the derivative portion.
y* 1
d * 1
x 1 px 1
px 1 p y
d
p
y
y* 1
d * 1 1
x 1
1 px 1
px 1 py
d
p
y
CES: σ
• And the other part: y* px
d *
x py
1
y * px 1
* , and
x* p y
y* px
p y
d x *
p x
d * y
x py
*
p y
d x *
p x
y
px px
1 1
1
py py
1 px 1
y*
1
x p 1 py
*
p
x
y
CES, Constant Elasticity of Substitution
• Bring the parts back together:
y* px
d * 1 1
1 1 1
1
1 1 px px
x py 1
1 1
=
px y* 1 p y py
d *
p x
y
• Yielding
1 1 1 1
11
1
1 1 px 1 1
1 py
1
, remember, ρ -1
1
1
, -1, 0
1
As , 0, perfect compliments
As 0, 1, Cobb-Douglas
As 1, , perfect substitutes
Simpler CES
• If we go with this simpler CES:
x y U x x 1
U we get MRS =
U y y 1
where 0, 1
y * px
d *
x py
Remember, *
px y
d *
p x
y
1
x p
Utility max requires x* and y* such that: 1 x
y py
1
y * px
1
So, at U-max: *
x p y
Simpler CES
• Which reduces to 1
1
1 px 1
1 py 1
1
1 1
px 1
py
1
, here, 1, 0
1
And this time
As , 0, perfect compliments
As 0, 1, Cobb-Douglas
As 1, , perfect substitutes
Cobb-Douglas
• Cobb-Douglas: U = Axαyβ
y
MRS
x Homothetic
• A monotonic transformation.
U 1
U T = ln ln x y
A
1
U T = ln x y
ln x y
UT =
m( ) ln x y
n( )
CES to Cobb-Douglas
• And with this
ln x y
UT =
m( ) ln x y
n( )
d
ln x y
ln x y d
So: lim lim
0 0 d
d
CES to Cobb-Douglas
• Derivatives and the limits
d
ln x y
d x ln x y ln y
lim = lim
0 d 0 x
y
d
x ln x y ln y
lim ln x ln y
0 x y
m( )
lim = ln x ln y ln x y
0 n( )
m( )
lim = ln x y
0 n( )
U ( )
So, lim ln
0
A
ln x y
e
lim ln
0 A
=e
ln x y
U ( )
lim ln
0 A
ln x y
Ae =Ae
U ( ) U ( )
lim ln ln U ( )
Ae 0 A
A lim e A
lim A li mU ( )
0 0
A 0
• Yielding
lim U ( ) =Ae
ln x y
0
lim U ( ) Ax y
0
10 O
Perfect Compliments
• U = min(αx, βy), where α, β >0
– Utility = the smaller of αx or βy
– Vertex where αx = βy, or where y/x = α/β
• Example: You always eat 3 T of Nutella with 2
slices of bread.
N on vert. axis, vertex
U = min(3B, 2N) where
N N/B = 3/2, or N = 3/2 B
When B = 2 and N = 3, U = 6
When B = 4 and N = 3, U = 6
When B = 2 and N = 6, U = 6
When B = 4 and N = 6, U = 12
Bread
Neoclassical Behavioral Assertion
• Consumers endeavor to maximize
U U ( xi )
where U(xi) represents the consumer’s own subjective
evaluation of derived from the consumption of goods
and services, xi.
• Under scarcity, consumers must choose among a limited
set of bundles described by the budget constraint
px i i M