We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPTX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 42
PHILOSOPHY OF
SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY
Why philosophy of science? Science is widely recognized as our most successful tool to investigate the world. However, we do not fully understand it yet! Some open philosophical problems: • Can one give a general definition of science? • What is the scientific method? And does it guarantee the success of science? • What is the relation between empirical facts and scientific theories? • What does constitute the progress of science? Why philosophy of space? Space plays a crucial role in our best physical theories, as well as in many other scientific disciplines However, we do not quite know what space really is! Some open philosophical problems: • How do we get to know space? • Is space an absolute entity, a sort of « container », independent from the material bodies it contains? • Or, is space a derived notion, which depends on the mutual relations between material bodies? • What geometry correctly describes space(-time)? Why philosophy of technology? Technology is pervasive in contemporary society. It is a product of science, which in different forms have contributed to the development of human kind. However, it poses very dramatic problems! Some open philosophical problems: • Can we control technological artefacts? And should we actually do so from a moral point of view? • What is the epistemological status of computer simulations and artificial intelligence? • What kind of information can we learn from non- material models and experiments? PHILOSOPHY & SCIENCE
Lecture 1
Science and Experience
September 14, 2023
Science and facts It is widely believed that the success of science is explained and justified by experience. That is, the truth of scientific statements is rooted on well-confirmed empirical facts
Commonsense view about scientific knowledge:
«Science is derived from the facts »
Is that really true? Is that so simple?
Objectivity of science Preliminary thesis on the methodology of science: one should first establish the facts and then build a theory to fit them.
• If the observations are carried out in a careful
and unprejudiced way, then the collected facts constitute an objective basis for science
• If the reasoning leading from such facts to
laws and theories is sound, then the resulting knowledge is objective. The factual basis of science Three claims about facts as the basis of science (Chalmers p.4):
• (a) Facts are directly given to careful,
unprejudiced observers via the senses • (b) Facts are prior to and independent of theory • (c) Facts constitute a firm and reliable foundation for scientific knowledge.
But are these claims true as they stand here?
What are scientific facts? Fact = claim about the world that can be directly established by means of observations.
A scientific fact is a linguistic statement that
expresses a certain state of affairs in the world, rather than that state of affairs itself. Only in this way facts can be part of a theory E.g. the statement « There are craters on the moon » is a scientific fact expressing the state of affairs that there are indeed craters on the moon. We are interested in observation statements , i.e. statements describing observable states of affairs. Against claim (a) Claim (a): Facts are directly given to careful, unprejudiced observers via the senses Observation by the senses is a subjective experience, and can therefore be different in different observers. E.g. even if an image forms in the retina of two observers in the same way, they may well disagree on what they see.
Furthermore, in science one has to learn how to
become a competent observer, E.g. using a microscope correctly requires practice Against claim (b) Claim (b) Facts are prior to and independent of theory Recording observable facts does not reduce to mere perception by a competent observer, but it requires an appropriate theoretical scheme to apply: That is the background (or prior) knowledge.
In fact, knowledge of a science is a prerequisite for
the formulation of the observation statements which constitute its factual basis: in other words, one may as well as say that « knowledge precedes facts » Learning how to observe When walking in a garden, a botanist will be able to collect many more observable facts about the flora than me, because she has a knowledge of botany. Against claim (c) Claim (c) Facts constitute a firm and reliable foundation for scientific knowledge. The subjectivity of perception undermines the reliability of the factual basis of science, in that different observers may disagree on what the observable states of affairs are.
Also, judgements on the adequacy of observation
statements draw on the background knowledge. This results in making such judgements fallible. Fallibility of observation: Example 1 The Greek philosopher Aristotle (384 – 322 BC) was the greatest authority in ancient science. He believed fire was one of the fundamental elements. With such a presupposition, the statement «the fire ascended » seems to be borned out by observation.
However, modern chemistry showed that this
is false: fire is not a substance, but the rapid oxidation of a material due to combustion. Fallibility of observation: Example 2 Before the Scientific Revolution (16th and17th centuries), the earth was believed not to move. The statement « Earth is stationary » actually appears to be supported by direct observations.
But we now know that Earth spins on its axis and
orbits around the sun. In order to realize it, it was necessary to anchor observations to the notion of inertia, which is a theoretical concept.
The Scientific Revolution changed what were
considered to be the observable facts of science! What is the factual basis of science? Observational statements are knowledge-dependent.
Yet, it does not mean that science does not have a
factual basis at all:
• observation is needed for testing,
i.e. to establish the truth of scientific statements.
• observational statements which are borne out
by direct experience constitute a significant factual basis for scientific knowledge. Main message so far Science has a factual basis in that scientific knowledge is grounded on observation. But the commonsense slogan «science is derived from the facts» is untenable:
• Observation is knowledge-dependent, and thus relative to the background of each observer. Problem: How can it be objective?
• Judgements on the truth of observation statements
rely on prior knowledge, hence they are fallible Problem: How can such statements be confirmed? Psychological account of observation A naive view of observation emphasizes the psychological, subjective nature of observation. Accordingly, the establishment of observational facts is
• Passive : the observers direct the senses towards an
object, let the information flow in and record what is there to be perceived • Private : an individual observer simply attends to what is presented to her by her subjective act of perception. But of course this subjectivist account of observation cannot be true in science!!! The nature of observation in science The fallibility of the senses makes the perceptual judgements of individuals unreliable. • Gathering observational data is not a merely passive recording of sensorial experiences: e.g. use of sophisticated instruments. • Observation is not private, else observers would have no access to each other’s perceptions, and hence the results could not be communicated Observations in science need to be carried out in such a way to eliminate, or at least reduce, subjectivity. Robert Hooke (1635-1703)
In 1665 Hooke published Micrographia , a book
containing the results of several observations he made with a microscope, and coined the term « cells » Repeatability of observations Early observations with the microscope led to disagreement among the scientists on what they saw
Hooke improved the instrument and the methods of
observation by varying the conditions of illuminatio The results he obtained could then be reproduced by different well-trained observers.
The repeatability of observations puts the scientific
community in a position to communicate observational statements as well as to test their truth. Galileo Galilei (1564-1642)
In 1609 he constructed a telescope to observe the
heavens. His aim was to confirm the Copernican theory Ptolemaic system
Geocentric model: Earth is steady at the center of the
universe and the Sun and the planets move around it. Copernican system
Heliocentric model: the Sun is at the center of the
universe and Earth and the planets move around it How can the Earth move? Problem for the Copernican theory: If the Earth orbits around the sun, then it seems that the moon should be left behind! However, even according to the Ptolemaic system Jupiter is supposed to move. So, if one could show that Jupiter has moons, then by analogy one would solve the problem about the motion of the Earth.
Jupiter’s moons are not visible to the naked eyes.
Thus, Galileo used a telescope with a scale attached to it so as to make accurate measurements. Jupiter’s moons
Galileo recorded daily histories of the four “starlets”
he observed and showed that his data were consistent with the assumption that such starlets are moons orbiting around Jupiter with a constant period. Galileo’s argument How could Galileo convince his opponents about the veracity of his observations with the telescope?
• If his observations were illusions, why should they
appear only next to Jupiter and nowhere else? • His measurement were consistent and repeatable. So, independent observers could verify his data • He could make further predictions on the positions of the moons as well as their transits and eclipses. Objective and fallible facts Galileo’s claims were based on observations which survived practical, objective tests and proved to be stronger than the other available alternatives. An observational statement can be included in the factual basis of science only if it is • objective : it can be tested by straightforward procedures which do not necessarily involve the subjective judgements of the observer • fallible : it may be undermined by new kinds of tests made possible by advancements in science and technology Relevant facts The observational facts that constitute the empirical basis of science must be relevant facts.
But how are such facts established?
• Which facts are relevant to a science depends on
the current state of development of that science
• Mere observation is not enough:
it is necessary to set up and perform experiments Example: Law of fall Galileo’s Two New Sciences (1634)
All heavy bodies fall at a constant acceleration
(on the surface of Earth that is the gravitational acceleration g = 9.8 m\s^2). If one could create a vacuum, any two falling bodies would travel the same distance in the same time. Example: Law of fall Galileo’s Two New Sciences (1634)
The law cannot be established by mere observation!
In fact, the presence of air resistance prevents a leave and a lead ball from falling in the same way. Need of experiments Many different processes are at work in the world, which interact with each other in complicated ways.
In order to acquire relevant facts, it is necessary to
intervene to isolate the process under investigation from the effects of other processes. This can only be done by setting up experiments.
Thus, the empirical basis of science is given by facts
which come from experimental results, and not just from observable facts. When are experiments adequate? Experiments are not straightforwardly given via the senses. They require expertise and practical trials and errors as well as sophisticated technologies. Furthermore, they ought to be adequate, that is • (1) the experimental set-up must be appropriate • (2) disturbing factors must be carefully eliminated
Insufficient theoretical knowledge about (1) and (2)
would lead to inadequate experimental results. Experiments are indeed theory-dependent. Fallibility of experimental results Experimental results are fallible:
• Progress in technology may make them outmoded
• Advancement in understanding may lead one to reject them as the instruments prove inadequate. • Changes in theoretical knowledge may lead one to regard them as irrelevant.
As a consequence, the experimental basis of science
is under constant transformation through history. Example: Electromagnetism
Electromagnetism is one of the fundamental
forces in nature. It arises from the mutual interactions between electric and magnetic fields James Clerk Maxwell (1831-1879)
Maxwell’s theory (1865) predicted the existence of
electromagnetic waves moving at the speed of light, and asserted that light itself is such a wave. Experimental challenges There were different theories about electromagnetic phenomena competing Maxwell’s own theory.
That challenged experimentalists to test some
empirical consequences of such theories.
To test and confirm Maxwell’s theory it was necessary
• to generate and detect electromagnetic radiations.
• to demonstrate that light is indeed an electromagnetic wave. • to check the prediction that all electromagnetic waves Heinrich Hertz (1857-1894)
He was the first to produce radio waves in 1886 and
his results confirmed Maxwell’s electromagnetic theory Hertz’s experiment
Hertz’s apparatus generated standing waves, which
enabled him to measure their wavelengths, and thereby to determine their velocity. Nonetheless, it also seemed that such waves could travel faster than light, thus contradicting Maxwell! On Hertz’s results It was Maxwell’s theory that made Hertz’s experimental results significant (theory-dependence).
Also, the observations he made using his apparatus
were accurate and his results were objective: In fact, anybody who could repeat the same experiments would obtain the same results.
But his experimental results were not fully adequate:
in his apparatus there were disturbance factors causing interference, as it was proven later on by means of more sophisticated experiment. The threat of circularity Threat of circularity: Scientific theories are appealed to in order to judge the adequacy of experimental results, but at the same time those experimental results are taken as evidence for confirmation of the scientific theories themselves
Problem: If that is true, experiments could not settle
any dispute between different competing theories! Can circularity be avoided? There are two possible ways to avoid the circularity arising from the theory-dependence of experiments
• Although the adequacy of an experiment needs to
be judged by some presupposed theory, the latter may not be identical to the theory under test. • Experimental results are determined by the world: the experimental outcomes necessary to test a theory depend just on the actual state of affairs of the world