SlideShare a Scribd company logo
Predicate Logic
First-Order Logic
Outline
• First-order logic
– Properties, relations, functions, quantifiers, …
– Terms, sentences, axioms, theories, proofs, …
• Extensions to first-order logic
• Logical agents
– Reflex agents
– Representing change: situation calculus, frame problem
– Preferences on actions
– Goal-based agents
predicate logic proposition logic FirstOrderLogic.ppt
Predicate Logic
• Predicate logic is an extension of propositional logic.
• A= The Ball’s color is Red ( propositional)
• Color(Ball,Red) Predicate is Color and Ball and Red are
argument.
• Rohan Likes Banana
• Likes(Rohan, Banana)
• Where likes is a predicate and rohan and banana are
argument
Predicate Logic
• Quantifies : We need include all and some
• Universal
∀
• Existential ∃
• Everybody loves somebody
• ∀x∃y
L(x,y)=loves(everybody,somebody)
First-order logic
• First-order logic (FOL) models the world in terms of
– Objects, which are things with individual identities
– Properties of objects that distinguish them from other objects
– Relations that hold among sets of objects
– Functions, which are a subset of relations where there is only one
“value” for any given “input”
• Examples:
– Objects: Students, lectures, companies, cars ...
– Relations: Brother-of, bigger-than, outside, part-of, has-color,
occurs-after, owns, visits, precedes, ...
– Properties: blue, oval, even, large, ...
– Functions: father-of, best-friend, second-half, one-more-than ...
predicate logic proposition logic FirstOrderLogic.ppt
predicate logic proposition logic FirstOrderLogic.ppt
predicate logic proposition logic FirstOrderLogic.ppt
User provides
• Constant symbols, which represent individuals in the world
– Mary
– 3
– Green
• Function symbols, which map individuals to individuals
– father-of(Mary) = John
– color-of(Sky) = Blue
• Predicate symbols, which map individuals to truth values
– greater(5,3)
– green(Grass)
– color(Grass, Green)
FOL Provides
• Variable symbols
– E.g., x, y, foo
• Connectives
– Same as in PL: not (), and (), or (), implies (), if
and only if (biconditional )
• Quantifiers
– Universal x or (Ax)
– Existential x or (Ex)
Sentences are built from terms and atoms
• A term (denoting a real-world individual) is a constant symbol, a
variable symbol, or an n-place function of n terms.
x and f(x1, ..., xn) are terms, where each xi is a term.
A term with no variables is a ground term
• An atomic sentence (which has value true or false) is an n-place
predicate of n terms
• A complex sentence is formed from atomic sentences connected
by the logical connectives:
P, PQ, PQ, PQ, PQ where P and Q are sentences
• A quantified sentence adds quantifiers  and 
• A well-formed formula (wff) is a sentence containing no “free”
variables. That is, all variables are “bound” by universal or
existential quantifiers.
(x)P(x,y) has x bound as a universally quantified variable, but y is free.
Quantifiers
• Universal quantification
– (x)P(x) means that P holds for all values of x in the
domain associated with that variable
– E.g., (x) dolphin(x)  mammal(x)
• Existential quantification
– ( x)P(x) means that P holds for some value of x in the
domain associated with that variable
– E.g., ( x) mammal(x)  lays-eggs(x)
– Permits one to make a statement about some object
without naming it
Quantifiers
• Universal quantifiers are often used with “implies” to form “rules”:
(x) student(x)  smart(x) means “All students are smart”
• Universal quantification is rarely used to make blanket statements
about every individual in the world:
(x)student(x)smart(x) means “Everyone in the world is a student and is smart”
• Existential quantifiers are usually used with “and” to specify a list of
properties about an individual:
(x) student(x)  smart(x) means “There is a student who is smart”
• A common mistake is to represent this English sentence as the FOL
sentence:
(x) student(x)  smart(x)
– But what happens when there is a person who is not a student?
Quantifier Scope
• Switching the order of universal quantifiers does not change
the meaning:
– (x)(y)P(x,y) ↔ (y)(x) P(x,y)
• Similarly, you can switch the order of existential
quantifiers:
– (x)(y)P(x,y) ↔ (y)(x) P(x,y)
• Switching the order of universals and existentials does
change meaning:
– Everyone likes someone: (x)(y) likes(x,y)
– Someone is liked by everyone: (y)(x) likes(x,y)
Connections between All and Exists
We can relate sentences involving  and 
using De Morgan’s laws:
(x) P(x) ↔ (x) P(x)
(x) P ↔ (x) P(x)
(x) P(x) ↔  (x) P(x)
(x) P(x) ↔ (x) P(x)
Quantified inference rules
• Universal instantiation
– x P(x)  P(A)
• Universal generalization
– P(A)  P(B) …  x P(x)
• Existential instantiation
– x P(x) P(F)  skolem constant F
• Existential generalization
– P(A)  x P(x)
Universal instantiation
(a.k.a. universal elimination)
• If (x) P(x) is true, then P(C) is true, where C is any
constant in the domain of x
• Example:
(x) eats(Ziggy, x)  eats(Ziggy, IceCream)
• The variable symbol can be replaced by any ground term,
i.e., any constant symbol or function symbol applied to
ground terms only
Existential instantiation
(a.k.a. existential elimination)
• From (x) P(x) infer P(c)
• Example:
– (x) eats(Ziggy, x)  eats(Ziggy, Stuff)
• Note that the variable is replaced by a brand-new constant
not occurring in this or any other sentence in the KB
• Also known as skolemization; constant is a skolem
constant
• In other words, we don’t want to accidentally draw other
inferences about it by introducing the constant
• Convenient to use this to reason about the unknown object,
rather than constantly manipulating the existential quantifier
Existential generalization
(a.k.a. existential introduction)
• If P(c) is true, then (x) P(x) is inferred.
• Example
eats(Ziggy, IceCream)  (x) eats(Ziggy, x)
• All instances of the given constant symbol are replaced by
the new variable symbol
• Note that the variable symbol cannot already exist
anywhere in the expression
Translating English to FOL
Every gardener likes the sun.
x gardener(x)  likes(x,Sun)
You can fool some of the people all of the time.
x t person(x) time(t)  can-fool(x,t)
You can fool all of the people some of the time.
x t (person(x)  time(t) can-fool(x,t))
x (person(x)  t (time(t) can-fool(x,t))
All purple mushrooms are poisonous.
x (mushroom(x)  purple(x))  poisonous(x)
No purple mushroom is poisonous.
x purple(x)  mushroom(x)  poisonous(x)
x (mushroom(x)  purple(x))  poisonous(x)
There are exactly two purple mushrooms.
x y mushroom(x)  purple(x)  mushroom(y)  purple(y) ^ (x=y)  z
(mushroom(z)  purple(z))  ((x=z)  (y=z))
Clinton is not tall.
tall(Clinton)
X is above Y iff X is on directly on top of Y or there is a pile of one or more other
objects directly on top of one another starting with X and ending with Y.
x y above(x,y) ↔ (on(x,y)  z (on(x,z)  above(z,y)))
Equivalent
Equivalent
Monty Python and The Art of Fallacy
Cast
–Sir Bedevere the Wise, master of (odd) logic
–King Arthur
–Villager 1, witch-hunter
–Villager 2, ex-newt
–Villager 3, one-line wonder
–All, the rest of you scoundrels, mongrels, and
nere-do-wells.
An example from Monty Python
by way of Russell & Norvig
• FIRST VILLAGER: We have found a witch. May we burn
her?
• ALL: A witch! Burn her!
• BEDEVERE: Why do you think she is a witch?
• SECOND VILLAGER: She turned me into a newt.
• B: A newt?
• V2 (after looking at himself for some time): I got better.
• ALL: Burn her anyway.
• B: Quiet! Quiet! There are ways of telling whether she is a
witch.
Monty Python cont.
• B: Tell me… what do you do with witches?
• ALL: Burn them!
• B: And what do you burn, apart from witches?
• Third Villager: …wood?
• B: So why do witches burn?
• V2 (after a beat): because they’re made of wood?
• B: Good.
• ALL: I see. Yes, of course.
Monty Python cont.
• B: So how can we tell if she is made of wood?
• V1: Make a bridge out of her.
• B: Ah… but can you not also make bridges out of stone?
• ALL: Yes, of course… um… er…
• B: Does wood sink in water?
• ALL: No, no, it floats. Throw her in the pond.
• B: Wait. Wait… tell me, what also floats on water?
• ALL: Bread? No, no no. Apples… gravy… very small
rocks…
• B: No, no, no,
Monty Python cont.
• KING ARTHUR: A duck!
• (They all turn and look at Arthur. Bedevere looks up, very
impressed.)
• B: Exactly. So… logically…
• V1 (beginning to pick up the thread): If she… weighs the
same as a duck… she’s made of wood.
• B: And therefore?
• ALL: A witch!
Monty Python Fallacy #1
• x witch(x)  burns(x)
• x wood(x)  burns(x)
• -------------------------------
•  z witch(x)  wood(x)
• p  q
• r  q
• ---------
• p  r Fallacy: Affirming the conclusion
Monty Python Near-Fallacy #2
• wood(x)  can-build-bridge(x)
• -----------------------------------------
•  can-build-bridge(x)  wood(x)
• B: Ah… but can you not also make bridges out of stone?
Monty Python Fallacy #3
• x wood(x)  floats(x)
• x duck-weight (x)  floats(x)
• -------------------------------
•  x duck-weight(x)  wood(x)
• p  q
• r  q
• -----------
•  r  p
Monty Python Fallacy #4
• z light(z)  wood(z)
• light(W)
• ------------------------------
•  wood(W) ok…………..
• witch(W)  wood(W) applying universal instan.
to fallacious conclusion #1
• wood(W)
• ---------------------------------
•  witch(z)
Example: A simple genealogy KB by FOL
• Build a small genealogy knowledge base using FOL that
– contains facts of immediate family relations (spouses, parents, etc.)
– contains definitions of more complex relations (ancestors, relatives)
– is able to answer queries about relationships between people
• Predicates:
– parent(x, y), child(x, y), father(x, y), daughter(x, y), etc.
– spouse(x, y), husband(x, y), wife(x,y)
– ancestor(x, y), descendant(x, y)
– male(x), female(y)
– relative(x, y)
• Facts:
– husband(Joe, Mary), son(Fred, Joe)
– spouse(John, Nancy), male(John), son(Mark, Nancy)
– father(Jack, Nancy), daughter(Linda, Jack)
– daughter(Liz, Linda)
– etc.
• Rules for genealogical relations
– (x,y) parent(x, y) ↔ child (y, x)
(x,y) father(x, y) ↔ parent(x, y)  male(x) (similarly for mother(x, y))
(x,y) daughter(x, y) ↔ child(x, y)  female(x) (similarly for son(x, y))
– (x,y) husband(x, y) ↔ spouse(x, y)  male(x) (similarly for wife(x, y))
(x,y) spouse(x, y) ↔ spouse(y, x) (spouse relation is symmetric)
– (x,y) parent(x, y)  ancestor(x, y)
(x,y)(z) parent(x, z)  ancestor(z, y)  ancestor(x, y)
– (x,y) descendant(x, y) ↔ ancestor(y, x)
– (x,y)(z) ancestor(z, x)  ancestor(z, y)  relative(x, y)
(related by common ancestry)
(x,y) spouse(x, y)  relative(x, y) (related by marriage)
(x,y)(z) relative(z, x)  relative(z, y)  relative(x, y) (transitive)
(x,y) relative(x, y) ↔ relative(y, x) (symmetric)
• Queries
– ancestor(Jack, Fred) /* the answer is yes */
– relative(Liz, Joe) /* the answer is yes */
– relative(Nancy, Matthew)
/* no answer in general, no if under closed world assumption */
– (z) ancestor(z, Fred)  ancestor(z, Liz)
Semantics of FOL
• Domain M: the set of all objects in the world (of interest)
• Interpretation I: includes
– Assign each constant to an object in M
– Define each function of n arguments as a mapping Mn => M
– Define each predicate of n arguments as a mapping Mn => {T, F}
– Therefore, every ground predicate with any instantiation will have a
truth value
– In general there is an infinite number of interpretations because |M| is
infinite
• Define logical connectives: ~, ^, , =>, <=> as in PL
• Define semantics of (x) and (x)
– (x) P(x) is true iff P(x) is true under all interpretations
– (x) P(x) is true iff P(x) is true under some interpretation
• Model: an interpretation of a set of sentences such that every
sentence is True
• A sentence is
– satisfiable if it is true under some interpretation
– valid if it is true under all possible interpretations
– inconsistent if there does not exist any interpretation under which the
sentence is true
• Logical consequence: S |= X if all models of S are also
models of X
Axioms, definitions and theorems
•Axioms are facts and rules that attempt to capture all of the
(important) facts and concepts about a domain; axioms can
be used to prove theorems
–Mathematicians don’t want any unnecessary (dependent) axioms –ones
that can be derived from other axioms
–Dependent axioms can make reasoning faster, however
–Choosing a good set of axioms for a domain is a kind of design
problem
•A definition of a predicate is of the form “p(X) ↔ …” and
can be decomposed into two parts
–Necessary description: “p(x)  …”
–Sufficient description “p(x)  …”
–Some concepts don’t have complete definitions (e.g., person(x))
More on definitions
• A necessary condition must be satisfied for a statement to be true.
• A sufficient condition, if satisfied, assures the statement’s truth.
• Duality: “P is sufficient for Q” is the same as “Q is necessary for P.”
• Examples: define father(x, y) by parent(x, y) and male(x)
– parent(x, y) is a necessary (but not sufficient) description of
father(x, y)
• father(x, y)  parent(x, y)
– parent(x, y) ^ male(x) ^ age(x, 35) is a sufficient (but not necessary)
description of father(x, y):
father(x, y)  parent(x, y) ^ male(x) ^ age(x, 35)
– parent(x, y) ^ male(x) is a necessary and sufficient description of
father(x, y)
parent(x, y) ^ male(x) ↔ father(x, y)
More on definitions
P(x)
S(x)
S(x) is a
necessary
condition of P(x)
(x) P(x) => S(x)
S(x)
P(x)
S(x) is a
sufficient
condition of P(x)
(x) P(x) <= S(x)
P(x)
S(x)
S(x) is a
necessary and
sufficient
condition of P(x)
(x) P(x) <=> S(x)
Higher-order logic
• FOL only allows to quantify over variables, and variables
can only range over objects.
• HOL allows us to quantify over relations
• Example: (quantify over functions)
“two functions are equal iff they produce the same value for all
arguments”
f g (f = g)  (x f(x) = g(x))
• Example: (quantify over predicates)
r transitive( r )  (xyz) r(x,y)  r(y,z)  r(x,z))
• More expressive, but undecidable. (there isn’t an effective
algorithm to decide whether all sentences are valid)
– First-order logic is decidable only when it uses predicates with only one
argument.
Expressing uniqueness
• Sometimes we want to say that there is a single, unique
object that satisfies a certain condition
• “There exists a unique x such that king(x) is true”
– x king(x)  y (king(y)  x=y)
– x king(x)  y (king(y)  xy)
– ! x king(x)
• “Every country has exactly one ruler”
– c country(c)  ! r ruler(c,r)
• Iota operator: “ x P(x)” means “the unique x such that p(x)
is true”
– “The unique ruler of Freedonia is dead”
– dead( x ruler(freedonia,x))
Notational differences
• Different symbols for and, or, not, implies, ...
–         
– p v (q ^ r)
– p + (q * r)
– etc
• Prolog
cat(X) :- furry(X), meows (X), has(X, claws)
• Lispy notations
(forall ?x (implies (and (furry ?x)
(meows ?x)
(has ?x claws))
(cat ?x)))
Logical agents for the Wumpus World
Three (non-exclusive) agent architectures:
–Reflex agents
• Have rules that classify situations, specifying how to
react to each possible situation
–Model-based agents
• Construct an internal model of their world
–Goal-based agents
• Form goals and try to achieve them
A simple reflex agent
• Rules to map percepts into observations:
b,g,u,c,t Percept([Stench, b, g, u, c], t)  Stench(t)
s,g,u,c,t Percept([s, Breeze, g, u, c], t)  Breeze(t)
s,b,u,c,t Percept([s, b, Glitter, u, c], t)  AtGold(t)
• Rules to select an action given observations:
t AtGold(t)  Action(Grab, t);
• Some difficulties:
– Consider Climb. There is no percept that indicates the agent should
climb out – position and holding gold are not part of the percept
sequence
– Loops – the percept will be repeated when you return to a square,
which should cause the same response (unless we maintain some
internal model of the world)
Representing change
• Representing change in the world in logic can be
tricky.
• One way is just to change the KB
– Add and delete sentences from the KB to reflect changes
– How do we remember the past, or reason about changes?
• Situation calculus is another way
• A situation is a snapshot of the world at some
instant in time
• When the agent performs an action A in
situation S1, the result is a new situation
S2.
Situations
Situation calculus
• A situation is a snapshot of the world at an interval of time during which
nothing changes
• Every true or false statement is made with respect to a particular situation.
– Add situation variables to every predicate.
– at(Agent,1,1) becomes at(Agent,1,1,s0): at(Agent,1,1) is true in situation (i.e., state)
s0.
– Alternatively, add a special 2nd-order predicate, holds(f,s), that means “f is true in
situation s.” E.g., holds(at(Agent,1,1),s0)
• Add a new function, result(a,s), that maps a situation s into a new situation as a
result of performing action a. For example, result(forward, s) is a function that
returns the successor state (situation) to s
• Example: The action agent-walks-to-location-y could be represented by
– (x)(y)(s) (at(Agent,x,s)  onbox(s))  at(Agent,y,result(walk(y),s))
Deducing hidden properties
• From the perceptual information we obtain in situations, we
can infer properties of locations
l,s at(Agent,l,s)  Breeze(s)  Breezy(l)
l,s at(Agent,l,s)  Stench(s)  Smelly(l)
• Neither Breezy nor Smelly need situation arguments
because pits and Wumpuses do not move around
Deducing hidden properties II
• We need to write some rules that relate various aspects of a
single world state (as opposed to across states)
• There are two main kinds of such rules:
– Causal rules reflect the assumed direction of causality in the world:
(l1,l2,s) At(Wumpus,l1,s)  Adjacent(l1,l2)  Smelly(l2)
( l1,l2,s) At(Pit,l1,s)  Adjacent(l1,l2)  Breezy(l2)
Systems that reason with causal rules are called model-based
reasoning systems
– Diagnostic rules infer the presence of hidden properties directly
from the percept-derived information. We have already seen two
diagnostic rules:
( l,s) At(Agent,l,s)  Breeze(s)  Breezy(l)
( l,s) At(Agent,l,s)  Stench(s)  Smelly(l)
Representing change:
The frame problem
• Frame axioms: If property x doesn’t change as a result of
applying action a in state s, then it stays the same.
– On (x, z, s)  Clear (x, s) 
On (x, table, Result(Move(x, table), s)) 
On(x, z, Result (Move (x, table), s))
– On (y, z, s)  y x  On (y, z, Result (Move (x, table), s))
– The proliferation of frame axioms becomes very cumbersome in
complex domains
The frame problem II
• Successor-state axiom: General statement that
characterizes every way in which a particular predicate can
become true:
– Either it can be made true, or it can already be true and not be
changed:
– On (x, table, Result(a,s)) 
[On (x, z, s)  Clear (x, s)  a = Move(x, table)] 
[On (x, table, s)  a  Move (x, z)]
• In complex worlds, where you want to reason about longer
chains of action, even these types of axioms are too
cumbersome
– Planning systems use special-purpose inference methods to reason
about the expected state of the world at any point in time during a
multi-step plan
Qualification problem
• Qualification problem:
– How can you possibly characterize every single effect of an action,
or every single exception that might occur?
– When I put my bread into the toaster, and push the button, it will
become toasted after two minutes, unless…
• The toaster is broken, or…
• The power is out, or…
• I blow a fuse, or…
• A neutron bomb explodes nearby and fries all electrical components,
or…
• A meteor strikes the earth, and the world we know it ceases to exist,
or…
Ramification problem
• Similarly, it’s just about impossible to characterize every side effect of
every action, at every possible level of detail:
– When I put my bread into the toaster, and push the button, the bread will
become toasted after two minutes, and…
• The crumbs that fall off the bread onto the bottom of the toaster over tray will
also become toasted, and…
• Some of the aforementioned crumbs will become burnt, and…
• The outside molecules of the bread will become “toasted,” and…
• The inside molecules of the bread will remain more “breadlike,” and…
• The toasting process will release a small amount of humidity into the air because
of evaporation, and…
• The heating elements will become a tiny fraction more likely to burn out the next
time I use the toaster, and…
• The electricity meter in the house will move up slightly, and…
Knowledge engineering!
• Modeling the “right” conditions and the “right” effects at
the “right” level of abstraction is very difficult
• Knowledge engineering (creating and maintaining
knowledge bases for intelligent reasoning) is an entire field
of investigation
• Many researchers hope that automated knowledge
acquisition and machine learning tools can fill the gap:
– Our intelligent systems should be able to learn about the conditions
and effects, just like we do!
– Our intelligent systems should be able to learn when to pay attention
to, or reason about, certain aspects of processes, depending on the
context!
Preferences among actions
• A problem with the Wumpus world knowledge base that we
have built so far is that it is difficult to decide which action
is best among a number of possibilities.
• For example, to decide between a forward and a grab,
axioms describing when it is OK to move to a square would
have to mention glitter.
• This is not modular!
• We can solve this problem by separating facts about
actions from facts about goals. This way our agent can be
reprogrammed just by asking it to achieve different
goals.
Preferences among actions
• The first step is to describe the desirability of actions
independent of each other.
• In doing this we will use a simple scale: actions can be
Great, Good, Medium, Risky, or Deadly.
• Obviously, the agent should always do the best action it can
find:
(a,s) Great(a,s)  Action(a,s)
(a,s) Good(a,s)  (b) Great(b,s)  Action(a,s)
(a,s) Medium(a,s)  ((b) Great(b,s)  Good(b,s))  Action(a,s)
...
Preferences among actions
• We use this action quality scale in the following way.
• Until it finds the gold, the basic strategy for our agent is:
– Great actions include picking up the gold when found and climbing
out of the cave with the gold.
– Good actions include moving to a square that’s OK and hasn't been
visited yet.
– Medium actions include moving to a square that is OK and has
already been visited.
– Risky actions include moving to a square that is not known to be
deadly or OK.
– Deadly actions are moving into a square that is known to have a pit
or a Wumpus.
Goal-based agents
• Once the gold is found, it is necessary to change strategies.
So now we need a new set of action values.
• We could encode this as a rule:
– (s) Holding(Gold,s)  GoalLocation([1,1]),s)
• We must now decide how the agent will work out a
sequence of actions to accomplish the goal.
• Three possible approaches are:
– Inference: good versus wasteful solutions
– Search: make a problem with operators and set of states
– Planning: to be discussed later

More Related Content

Similar to predicate logic proposition logic FirstOrderLogic.ppt (20)

PPT
basic knowledge represenatation in first order logic
chougulesup79
 
PPTX
Knowledge Representation and Reasoning.pptx
MohanKumarP34
 
PPTX
Chapter 1.4.pptx Chapter 1.4.pptx DISCREATE MATH
JessylyneSophia
 
PPT
Lecture in predecate logical propostions
Kamal El-Saady
 
PPTX
Natural language processing: word senses and relations
ranjitkolkar1
 
PPTX
Lecture in the topic of Predicate Calculus.pptx
Kamal El-Saady
 
PPT
X02PredCalculus.ppt
MalligaarjunanN
 
PDF
Logic
Shiwani Gupta
 
PPTX
Lecture in the predicates-quantifiers.pptx
Kamal El-Saady
 
PPT
3 fol examples v2
Digvijay Singh
 
PPTX
Translation to QL Part 1
Nat Karablina
 
PPT
PredicateLogic (1).ppt
keerthana592112
 
PPTX
PredicateLogic.pptx
santhosh sriprada
 
PDF
unit-3 First half..pdf nice ppt helps in ai intelligence
akshay04282004
 
PDF
Chapter 01 - p2.pdf
smarwaneid
 
PDF
16_FirstOrderLogic.p_4_moduleModuleNotespdf
ShylaBg1
 
PPT
Frstorder 9 sldes read
Yasir Khan
 
PDF
Lec 3.pdf
ZainabShahzad9
 
PPT
Predicates and Quantifiers
blaircomp2003
 
PPT
Inference in first-order logic Reducing first-order
erasmuskratos
 
basic knowledge represenatation in first order logic
chougulesup79
 
Knowledge Representation and Reasoning.pptx
MohanKumarP34
 
Chapter 1.4.pptx Chapter 1.4.pptx DISCREATE MATH
JessylyneSophia
 
Lecture in predecate logical propostions
Kamal El-Saady
 
Natural language processing: word senses and relations
ranjitkolkar1
 
Lecture in the topic of Predicate Calculus.pptx
Kamal El-Saady
 
X02PredCalculus.ppt
MalligaarjunanN
 
Lecture in the predicates-quantifiers.pptx
Kamal El-Saady
 
3 fol examples v2
Digvijay Singh
 
Translation to QL Part 1
Nat Karablina
 
PredicateLogic (1).ppt
keerthana592112
 
PredicateLogic.pptx
santhosh sriprada
 
unit-3 First half..pdf nice ppt helps in ai intelligence
akshay04282004
 
Chapter 01 - p2.pdf
smarwaneid
 
16_FirstOrderLogic.p_4_moduleModuleNotespdf
ShylaBg1
 
Frstorder 9 sldes read
Yasir Khan
 
Lec 3.pdf
ZainabShahzad9
 
Predicates and Quantifiers
blaircomp2003
 
Inference in first-order logic Reducing first-order
erasmuskratos
 

More from SuryaBasnet3 (20)

PPT
Operating System task and sub task system call ch2 system call.ppt
SuryaBasnet3
 
PDF
Operating System File Management disk_management.pdf
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPTX
Management Information system laudon_ess10e_pp_3.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPT
business information system CRM and Supply chain management .ppt
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPTX
A modern approach to AI AI_02_agents_Strut.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPTX
Introduction to Artificial Intelligence 01_intro.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPTX
Operating System File System IMpl lecture19.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPTX
Laudon and Traver Unit 3 17th edition.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPTX
cryptography and Network Security AES.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPT
crypto Digital Signature Diffie Hell man.ppt
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPT
Block Cipher Stream Cipher DESUnit 3.ppt
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPTX
E-governance framework and its evolutions Chapter 2.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPTX
[CS161 FA23] Lecture 1_ Introduction and Security Principles.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPTX
introduction to information technology Chapter I.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPTX
Information system within organization Chapter VI.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPTX
Business Information SystemChapter VI.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPTX
Adhit_presentation_Searching_Algorithm(BFS,DFS).pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPTX
cloud computer security fundamentals Unit-5.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
PPTX
Cloud computing and different and its types Unit-2.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
DOCX
E-Democracy.docx E Governance and digital Governance in AI era
SuryaBasnet3
 
Operating System task and sub task system call ch2 system call.ppt
SuryaBasnet3
 
Operating System File Management disk_management.pdf
SuryaBasnet3
 
Management Information system laudon_ess10e_pp_3.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
business information system CRM and Supply chain management .ppt
SuryaBasnet3
 
A modern approach to AI AI_02_agents_Strut.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
Introduction to Artificial Intelligence 01_intro.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
Operating System File System IMpl lecture19.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
Laudon and Traver Unit 3 17th edition.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
cryptography and Network Security AES.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
crypto Digital Signature Diffie Hell man.ppt
SuryaBasnet3
 
Block Cipher Stream Cipher DESUnit 3.ppt
SuryaBasnet3
 
E-governance framework and its evolutions Chapter 2.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
[CS161 FA23] Lecture 1_ Introduction and Security Principles.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
introduction to information technology Chapter I.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
Information system within organization Chapter VI.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
Business Information SystemChapter VI.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
Adhit_presentation_Searching_Algorithm(BFS,DFS).pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
cloud computer security fundamentals Unit-5.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
Cloud computing and different and its types Unit-2.pptx
SuryaBasnet3
 
E-Democracy.docx E Governance and digital Governance in AI era
SuryaBasnet3
 
Ad

Recently uploaded (20)

PDF
AI-Powered-Visual-Storytelling-for-Nonprofits.pdf
TechSoup
 
PPT
Indian Contract Act 1872, Business Law #MBA #BBA #BCOM
priyasinghy107
 
PPTX
Identifying elements in the story. Arrange the events in the story
geraldineamahido2
 
PDF
Android Programming - Basics of Mobile App, App tools and Android Basics
Kavitha P.V
 
PDF
Characteristics, Strengths and Weaknesses of Quantitative Research.pdf
Thelma Villaflores
 
PPTX
EDUCATIONAL MEDIA/ TEACHING AUDIO VISUAL AIDS
Sonali Gupta
 
PPTX
SD_GMRC5_Session 6AB_Dulog Pedagohikal at Pagtataya (1).pptx
NickeyArguelles
 
PPTX
infertility, types,causes, impact, and management
Ritu480198
 
PPTX
ENG8_Q1_WEEK2_LESSON1. Presentation pptx
marawehsvinetshe
 
PPTX
Difference between write and update in odoo 18
Celine George
 
PPTX
How to Send Email From Odoo 18 Website - Odoo Slides
Celine George
 
PDF
Is Assignment Help Legal in Australia_.pdf
thomas19williams83
 
PDF
Women's Health: Essential Tips for Every Stage.pdf
Iftikhar Ahmed
 
PPTX
How to Create a Customer From Website in Odoo 18.pptx
Celine George
 
PDF
Workbook de Inglés Completo - English Path.pdf
shityouenglishpath
 
PDF
Stokey: A Jewish Village by Rachel Kolsky
History of Stoke Newington
 
PPTX
ENGlish 8 lesson presentation PowerPoint.pptx
marawehsvinetshe
 
PPTX
Post Dated Cheque(PDC) Management in Odoo 18
Celine George
 
PPTX
Light Reflection and Refraction- Activities - Class X Science
SONU ACADEMY
 
PPTX
DAY 1_QUARTER1 ENGLISH 5 WEEK- PRESENTATION.pptx
BanyMacalintal
 
AI-Powered-Visual-Storytelling-for-Nonprofits.pdf
TechSoup
 
Indian Contract Act 1872, Business Law #MBA #BBA #BCOM
priyasinghy107
 
Identifying elements in the story. Arrange the events in the story
geraldineamahido2
 
Android Programming - Basics of Mobile App, App tools and Android Basics
Kavitha P.V
 
Characteristics, Strengths and Weaknesses of Quantitative Research.pdf
Thelma Villaflores
 
EDUCATIONAL MEDIA/ TEACHING AUDIO VISUAL AIDS
Sonali Gupta
 
SD_GMRC5_Session 6AB_Dulog Pedagohikal at Pagtataya (1).pptx
NickeyArguelles
 
infertility, types,causes, impact, and management
Ritu480198
 
ENG8_Q1_WEEK2_LESSON1. Presentation pptx
marawehsvinetshe
 
Difference between write and update in odoo 18
Celine George
 
How to Send Email From Odoo 18 Website - Odoo Slides
Celine George
 
Is Assignment Help Legal in Australia_.pdf
thomas19williams83
 
Women's Health: Essential Tips for Every Stage.pdf
Iftikhar Ahmed
 
How to Create a Customer From Website in Odoo 18.pptx
Celine George
 
Workbook de Inglés Completo - English Path.pdf
shityouenglishpath
 
Stokey: A Jewish Village by Rachel Kolsky
History of Stoke Newington
 
ENGlish 8 lesson presentation PowerPoint.pptx
marawehsvinetshe
 
Post Dated Cheque(PDC) Management in Odoo 18
Celine George
 
Light Reflection and Refraction- Activities - Class X Science
SONU ACADEMY
 
DAY 1_QUARTER1 ENGLISH 5 WEEK- PRESENTATION.pptx
BanyMacalintal
 
Ad

predicate logic proposition logic FirstOrderLogic.ppt

  • 2. Outline • First-order logic – Properties, relations, functions, quantifiers, … – Terms, sentences, axioms, theories, proofs, … • Extensions to first-order logic • Logical agents – Reflex agents – Representing change: situation calculus, frame problem – Preferences on actions – Goal-based agents
  • 4. Predicate Logic • Predicate logic is an extension of propositional logic. • A= The Ball’s color is Red ( propositional) • Color(Ball,Red) Predicate is Color and Ball and Red are argument. • Rohan Likes Banana • Likes(Rohan, Banana) • Where likes is a predicate and rohan and banana are argument
  • 5. Predicate Logic • Quantifies : We need include all and some • Universal ∀ • Existential ∃ • Everybody loves somebody • ∀x∃y L(x,y)=loves(everybody,somebody)
  • 6. First-order logic • First-order logic (FOL) models the world in terms of – Objects, which are things with individual identities – Properties of objects that distinguish them from other objects – Relations that hold among sets of objects – Functions, which are a subset of relations where there is only one “value” for any given “input” • Examples: – Objects: Students, lectures, companies, cars ... – Relations: Brother-of, bigger-than, outside, part-of, has-color, occurs-after, owns, visits, precedes, ... – Properties: blue, oval, even, large, ... – Functions: father-of, best-friend, second-half, one-more-than ...
  • 10. User provides • Constant symbols, which represent individuals in the world – Mary – 3 – Green • Function symbols, which map individuals to individuals – father-of(Mary) = John – color-of(Sky) = Blue • Predicate symbols, which map individuals to truth values – greater(5,3) – green(Grass) – color(Grass, Green)
  • 11. FOL Provides • Variable symbols – E.g., x, y, foo • Connectives – Same as in PL: not (), and (), or (), implies (), if and only if (biconditional ) • Quantifiers – Universal x or (Ax) – Existential x or (Ex)
  • 12. Sentences are built from terms and atoms • A term (denoting a real-world individual) is a constant symbol, a variable symbol, or an n-place function of n terms. x and f(x1, ..., xn) are terms, where each xi is a term. A term with no variables is a ground term • An atomic sentence (which has value true or false) is an n-place predicate of n terms • A complex sentence is formed from atomic sentences connected by the logical connectives: P, PQ, PQ, PQ, PQ where P and Q are sentences • A quantified sentence adds quantifiers  and  • A well-formed formula (wff) is a sentence containing no “free” variables. That is, all variables are “bound” by universal or existential quantifiers. (x)P(x,y) has x bound as a universally quantified variable, but y is free.
  • 13. Quantifiers • Universal quantification – (x)P(x) means that P holds for all values of x in the domain associated with that variable – E.g., (x) dolphin(x)  mammal(x) • Existential quantification – ( x)P(x) means that P holds for some value of x in the domain associated with that variable – E.g., ( x) mammal(x)  lays-eggs(x) – Permits one to make a statement about some object without naming it
  • 14. Quantifiers • Universal quantifiers are often used with “implies” to form “rules”: (x) student(x)  smart(x) means “All students are smart” • Universal quantification is rarely used to make blanket statements about every individual in the world: (x)student(x)smart(x) means “Everyone in the world is a student and is smart” • Existential quantifiers are usually used with “and” to specify a list of properties about an individual: (x) student(x)  smart(x) means “There is a student who is smart” • A common mistake is to represent this English sentence as the FOL sentence: (x) student(x)  smart(x) – But what happens when there is a person who is not a student?
  • 15. Quantifier Scope • Switching the order of universal quantifiers does not change the meaning: – (x)(y)P(x,y) ↔ (y)(x) P(x,y) • Similarly, you can switch the order of existential quantifiers: – (x)(y)P(x,y) ↔ (y)(x) P(x,y) • Switching the order of universals and existentials does change meaning: – Everyone likes someone: (x)(y) likes(x,y) – Someone is liked by everyone: (y)(x) likes(x,y)
  • 16. Connections between All and Exists We can relate sentences involving  and  using De Morgan’s laws: (x) P(x) ↔ (x) P(x) (x) P ↔ (x) P(x) (x) P(x) ↔  (x) P(x) (x) P(x) ↔ (x) P(x)
  • 17. Quantified inference rules • Universal instantiation – x P(x)  P(A) • Universal generalization – P(A)  P(B) …  x P(x) • Existential instantiation – x P(x) P(F)  skolem constant F • Existential generalization – P(A)  x P(x)
  • 18. Universal instantiation (a.k.a. universal elimination) • If (x) P(x) is true, then P(C) is true, where C is any constant in the domain of x • Example: (x) eats(Ziggy, x)  eats(Ziggy, IceCream) • The variable symbol can be replaced by any ground term, i.e., any constant symbol or function symbol applied to ground terms only
  • 19. Existential instantiation (a.k.a. existential elimination) • From (x) P(x) infer P(c) • Example: – (x) eats(Ziggy, x)  eats(Ziggy, Stuff) • Note that the variable is replaced by a brand-new constant not occurring in this or any other sentence in the KB • Also known as skolemization; constant is a skolem constant • In other words, we don’t want to accidentally draw other inferences about it by introducing the constant • Convenient to use this to reason about the unknown object, rather than constantly manipulating the existential quantifier
  • 20. Existential generalization (a.k.a. existential introduction) • If P(c) is true, then (x) P(x) is inferred. • Example eats(Ziggy, IceCream)  (x) eats(Ziggy, x) • All instances of the given constant symbol are replaced by the new variable symbol • Note that the variable symbol cannot already exist anywhere in the expression
  • 21. Translating English to FOL Every gardener likes the sun. x gardener(x)  likes(x,Sun) You can fool some of the people all of the time. x t person(x) time(t)  can-fool(x,t) You can fool all of the people some of the time. x t (person(x)  time(t) can-fool(x,t)) x (person(x)  t (time(t) can-fool(x,t)) All purple mushrooms are poisonous. x (mushroom(x)  purple(x))  poisonous(x) No purple mushroom is poisonous. x purple(x)  mushroom(x)  poisonous(x) x (mushroom(x)  purple(x))  poisonous(x) There are exactly two purple mushrooms. x y mushroom(x)  purple(x)  mushroom(y)  purple(y) ^ (x=y)  z (mushroom(z)  purple(z))  ((x=z)  (y=z)) Clinton is not tall. tall(Clinton) X is above Y iff X is on directly on top of Y or there is a pile of one or more other objects directly on top of one another starting with X and ending with Y. x y above(x,y) ↔ (on(x,y)  z (on(x,z)  above(z,y))) Equivalent Equivalent
  • 22. Monty Python and The Art of Fallacy Cast –Sir Bedevere the Wise, master of (odd) logic –King Arthur –Villager 1, witch-hunter –Villager 2, ex-newt –Villager 3, one-line wonder –All, the rest of you scoundrels, mongrels, and nere-do-wells.
  • 23. An example from Monty Python by way of Russell & Norvig • FIRST VILLAGER: We have found a witch. May we burn her? • ALL: A witch! Burn her! • BEDEVERE: Why do you think she is a witch? • SECOND VILLAGER: She turned me into a newt. • B: A newt? • V2 (after looking at himself for some time): I got better. • ALL: Burn her anyway. • B: Quiet! Quiet! There are ways of telling whether she is a witch.
  • 24. Monty Python cont. • B: Tell me… what do you do with witches? • ALL: Burn them! • B: And what do you burn, apart from witches? • Third Villager: …wood? • B: So why do witches burn? • V2 (after a beat): because they’re made of wood? • B: Good. • ALL: I see. Yes, of course.
  • 25. Monty Python cont. • B: So how can we tell if she is made of wood? • V1: Make a bridge out of her. • B: Ah… but can you not also make bridges out of stone? • ALL: Yes, of course… um… er… • B: Does wood sink in water? • ALL: No, no, it floats. Throw her in the pond. • B: Wait. Wait… tell me, what also floats on water? • ALL: Bread? No, no no. Apples… gravy… very small rocks… • B: No, no, no,
  • 26. Monty Python cont. • KING ARTHUR: A duck! • (They all turn and look at Arthur. Bedevere looks up, very impressed.) • B: Exactly. So… logically… • V1 (beginning to pick up the thread): If she… weighs the same as a duck… she’s made of wood. • B: And therefore? • ALL: A witch!
  • 27. Monty Python Fallacy #1 • x witch(x)  burns(x) • x wood(x)  burns(x) • ------------------------------- •  z witch(x)  wood(x) • p  q • r  q • --------- • p  r Fallacy: Affirming the conclusion
  • 28. Monty Python Near-Fallacy #2 • wood(x)  can-build-bridge(x) • ----------------------------------------- •  can-build-bridge(x)  wood(x) • B: Ah… but can you not also make bridges out of stone?
  • 29. Monty Python Fallacy #3 • x wood(x)  floats(x) • x duck-weight (x)  floats(x) • ------------------------------- •  x duck-weight(x)  wood(x) • p  q • r  q • ----------- •  r  p
  • 30. Monty Python Fallacy #4 • z light(z)  wood(z) • light(W) • ------------------------------ •  wood(W) ok………….. • witch(W)  wood(W) applying universal instan. to fallacious conclusion #1 • wood(W) • --------------------------------- •  witch(z)
  • 31. Example: A simple genealogy KB by FOL • Build a small genealogy knowledge base using FOL that – contains facts of immediate family relations (spouses, parents, etc.) – contains definitions of more complex relations (ancestors, relatives) – is able to answer queries about relationships between people • Predicates: – parent(x, y), child(x, y), father(x, y), daughter(x, y), etc. – spouse(x, y), husband(x, y), wife(x,y) – ancestor(x, y), descendant(x, y) – male(x), female(y) – relative(x, y) • Facts: – husband(Joe, Mary), son(Fred, Joe) – spouse(John, Nancy), male(John), son(Mark, Nancy) – father(Jack, Nancy), daughter(Linda, Jack) – daughter(Liz, Linda) – etc.
  • 32. • Rules for genealogical relations – (x,y) parent(x, y) ↔ child (y, x) (x,y) father(x, y) ↔ parent(x, y)  male(x) (similarly for mother(x, y)) (x,y) daughter(x, y) ↔ child(x, y)  female(x) (similarly for son(x, y)) – (x,y) husband(x, y) ↔ spouse(x, y)  male(x) (similarly for wife(x, y)) (x,y) spouse(x, y) ↔ spouse(y, x) (spouse relation is symmetric) – (x,y) parent(x, y)  ancestor(x, y) (x,y)(z) parent(x, z)  ancestor(z, y)  ancestor(x, y) – (x,y) descendant(x, y) ↔ ancestor(y, x) – (x,y)(z) ancestor(z, x)  ancestor(z, y)  relative(x, y) (related by common ancestry) (x,y) spouse(x, y)  relative(x, y) (related by marriage) (x,y)(z) relative(z, x)  relative(z, y)  relative(x, y) (transitive) (x,y) relative(x, y) ↔ relative(y, x) (symmetric) • Queries – ancestor(Jack, Fred) /* the answer is yes */ – relative(Liz, Joe) /* the answer is yes */ – relative(Nancy, Matthew) /* no answer in general, no if under closed world assumption */ – (z) ancestor(z, Fred)  ancestor(z, Liz)
  • 33. Semantics of FOL • Domain M: the set of all objects in the world (of interest) • Interpretation I: includes – Assign each constant to an object in M – Define each function of n arguments as a mapping Mn => M – Define each predicate of n arguments as a mapping Mn => {T, F} – Therefore, every ground predicate with any instantiation will have a truth value – In general there is an infinite number of interpretations because |M| is infinite • Define logical connectives: ~, ^, , =>, <=> as in PL • Define semantics of (x) and (x) – (x) P(x) is true iff P(x) is true under all interpretations – (x) P(x) is true iff P(x) is true under some interpretation
  • 34. • Model: an interpretation of a set of sentences such that every sentence is True • A sentence is – satisfiable if it is true under some interpretation – valid if it is true under all possible interpretations – inconsistent if there does not exist any interpretation under which the sentence is true • Logical consequence: S |= X if all models of S are also models of X
  • 35. Axioms, definitions and theorems •Axioms are facts and rules that attempt to capture all of the (important) facts and concepts about a domain; axioms can be used to prove theorems –Mathematicians don’t want any unnecessary (dependent) axioms –ones that can be derived from other axioms –Dependent axioms can make reasoning faster, however –Choosing a good set of axioms for a domain is a kind of design problem •A definition of a predicate is of the form “p(X) ↔ …” and can be decomposed into two parts –Necessary description: “p(x)  …” –Sufficient description “p(x)  …” –Some concepts don’t have complete definitions (e.g., person(x))
  • 36. More on definitions • A necessary condition must be satisfied for a statement to be true. • A sufficient condition, if satisfied, assures the statement’s truth. • Duality: “P is sufficient for Q” is the same as “Q is necessary for P.” • Examples: define father(x, y) by parent(x, y) and male(x) – parent(x, y) is a necessary (but not sufficient) description of father(x, y) • father(x, y)  parent(x, y) – parent(x, y) ^ male(x) ^ age(x, 35) is a sufficient (but not necessary) description of father(x, y): father(x, y)  parent(x, y) ^ male(x) ^ age(x, 35) – parent(x, y) ^ male(x) is a necessary and sufficient description of father(x, y) parent(x, y) ^ male(x) ↔ father(x, y)
  • 37. More on definitions P(x) S(x) S(x) is a necessary condition of P(x) (x) P(x) => S(x) S(x) P(x) S(x) is a sufficient condition of P(x) (x) P(x) <= S(x) P(x) S(x) S(x) is a necessary and sufficient condition of P(x) (x) P(x) <=> S(x)
  • 38. Higher-order logic • FOL only allows to quantify over variables, and variables can only range over objects. • HOL allows us to quantify over relations • Example: (quantify over functions) “two functions are equal iff they produce the same value for all arguments” f g (f = g)  (x f(x) = g(x)) • Example: (quantify over predicates) r transitive( r )  (xyz) r(x,y)  r(y,z)  r(x,z)) • More expressive, but undecidable. (there isn’t an effective algorithm to decide whether all sentences are valid) – First-order logic is decidable only when it uses predicates with only one argument.
  • 39. Expressing uniqueness • Sometimes we want to say that there is a single, unique object that satisfies a certain condition • “There exists a unique x such that king(x) is true” – x king(x)  y (king(y)  x=y) – x king(x)  y (king(y)  xy) – ! x king(x) • “Every country has exactly one ruler” – c country(c)  ! r ruler(c,r) • Iota operator: “ x P(x)” means “the unique x such that p(x) is true” – “The unique ruler of Freedonia is dead” – dead( x ruler(freedonia,x))
  • 40. Notational differences • Different symbols for and, or, not, implies, ... –          – p v (q ^ r) – p + (q * r) – etc • Prolog cat(X) :- furry(X), meows (X), has(X, claws) • Lispy notations (forall ?x (implies (and (furry ?x) (meows ?x) (has ?x claws)) (cat ?x)))
  • 41. Logical agents for the Wumpus World Three (non-exclusive) agent architectures: –Reflex agents • Have rules that classify situations, specifying how to react to each possible situation –Model-based agents • Construct an internal model of their world –Goal-based agents • Form goals and try to achieve them
  • 42. A simple reflex agent • Rules to map percepts into observations: b,g,u,c,t Percept([Stench, b, g, u, c], t)  Stench(t) s,g,u,c,t Percept([s, Breeze, g, u, c], t)  Breeze(t) s,b,u,c,t Percept([s, b, Glitter, u, c], t)  AtGold(t) • Rules to select an action given observations: t AtGold(t)  Action(Grab, t); • Some difficulties: – Consider Climb. There is no percept that indicates the agent should climb out – position and holding gold are not part of the percept sequence – Loops – the percept will be repeated when you return to a square, which should cause the same response (unless we maintain some internal model of the world)
  • 43. Representing change • Representing change in the world in logic can be tricky. • One way is just to change the KB – Add and delete sentences from the KB to reflect changes – How do we remember the past, or reason about changes? • Situation calculus is another way • A situation is a snapshot of the world at some instant in time • When the agent performs an action A in situation S1, the result is a new situation S2.
  • 45. Situation calculus • A situation is a snapshot of the world at an interval of time during which nothing changes • Every true or false statement is made with respect to a particular situation. – Add situation variables to every predicate. – at(Agent,1,1) becomes at(Agent,1,1,s0): at(Agent,1,1) is true in situation (i.e., state) s0. – Alternatively, add a special 2nd-order predicate, holds(f,s), that means “f is true in situation s.” E.g., holds(at(Agent,1,1),s0) • Add a new function, result(a,s), that maps a situation s into a new situation as a result of performing action a. For example, result(forward, s) is a function that returns the successor state (situation) to s • Example: The action agent-walks-to-location-y could be represented by – (x)(y)(s) (at(Agent,x,s)  onbox(s))  at(Agent,y,result(walk(y),s))
  • 46. Deducing hidden properties • From the perceptual information we obtain in situations, we can infer properties of locations l,s at(Agent,l,s)  Breeze(s)  Breezy(l) l,s at(Agent,l,s)  Stench(s)  Smelly(l) • Neither Breezy nor Smelly need situation arguments because pits and Wumpuses do not move around
  • 47. Deducing hidden properties II • We need to write some rules that relate various aspects of a single world state (as opposed to across states) • There are two main kinds of such rules: – Causal rules reflect the assumed direction of causality in the world: (l1,l2,s) At(Wumpus,l1,s)  Adjacent(l1,l2)  Smelly(l2) ( l1,l2,s) At(Pit,l1,s)  Adjacent(l1,l2)  Breezy(l2) Systems that reason with causal rules are called model-based reasoning systems – Diagnostic rules infer the presence of hidden properties directly from the percept-derived information. We have already seen two diagnostic rules: ( l,s) At(Agent,l,s)  Breeze(s)  Breezy(l) ( l,s) At(Agent,l,s)  Stench(s)  Smelly(l)
  • 48. Representing change: The frame problem • Frame axioms: If property x doesn’t change as a result of applying action a in state s, then it stays the same. – On (x, z, s)  Clear (x, s)  On (x, table, Result(Move(x, table), s))  On(x, z, Result (Move (x, table), s)) – On (y, z, s)  y x  On (y, z, Result (Move (x, table), s)) – The proliferation of frame axioms becomes very cumbersome in complex domains
  • 49. The frame problem II • Successor-state axiom: General statement that characterizes every way in which a particular predicate can become true: – Either it can be made true, or it can already be true and not be changed: – On (x, table, Result(a,s))  [On (x, z, s)  Clear (x, s)  a = Move(x, table)]  [On (x, table, s)  a  Move (x, z)] • In complex worlds, where you want to reason about longer chains of action, even these types of axioms are too cumbersome – Planning systems use special-purpose inference methods to reason about the expected state of the world at any point in time during a multi-step plan
  • 50. Qualification problem • Qualification problem: – How can you possibly characterize every single effect of an action, or every single exception that might occur? – When I put my bread into the toaster, and push the button, it will become toasted after two minutes, unless… • The toaster is broken, or… • The power is out, or… • I blow a fuse, or… • A neutron bomb explodes nearby and fries all electrical components, or… • A meteor strikes the earth, and the world we know it ceases to exist, or…
  • 51. Ramification problem • Similarly, it’s just about impossible to characterize every side effect of every action, at every possible level of detail: – When I put my bread into the toaster, and push the button, the bread will become toasted after two minutes, and… • The crumbs that fall off the bread onto the bottom of the toaster over tray will also become toasted, and… • Some of the aforementioned crumbs will become burnt, and… • The outside molecules of the bread will become “toasted,” and… • The inside molecules of the bread will remain more “breadlike,” and… • The toasting process will release a small amount of humidity into the air because of evaporation, and… • The heating elements will become a tiny fraction more likely to burn out the next time I use the toaster, and… • The electricity meter in the house will move up slightly, and…
  • 52. Knowledge engineering! • Modeling the “right” conditions and the “right” effects at the “right” level of abstraction is very difficult • Knowledge engineering (creating and maintaining knowledge bases for intelligent reasoning) is an entire field of investigation • Many researchers hope that automated knowledge acquisition and machine learning tools can fill the gap: – Our intelligent systems should be able to learn about the conditions and effects, just like we do! – Our intelligent systems should be able to learn when to pay attention to, or reason about, certain aspects of processes, depending on the context!
  • 53. Preferences among actions • A problem with the Wumpus world knowledge base that we have built so far is that it is difficult to decide which action is best among a number of possibilities. • For example, to decide between a forward and a grab, axioms describing when it is OK to move to a square would have to mention glitter. • This is not modular! • We can solve this problem by separating facts about actions from facts about goals. This way our agent can be reprogrammed just by asking it to achieve different goals.
  • 54. Preferences among actions • The first step is to describe the desirability of actions independent of each other. • In doing this we will use a simple scale: actions can be Great, Good, Medium, Risky, or Deadly. • Obviously, the agent should always do the best action it can find: (a,s) Great(a,s)  Action(a,s) (a,s) Good(a,s)  (b) Great(b,s)  Action(a,s) (a,s) Medium(a,s)  ((b) Great(b,s)  Good(b,s))  Action(a,s) ...
  • 55. Preferences among actions • We use this action quality scale in the following way. • Until it finds the gold, the basic strategy for our agent is: – Great actions include picking up the gold when found and climbing out of the cave with the gold. – Good actions include moving to a square that’s OK and hasn't been visited yet. – Medium actions include moving to a square that is OK and has already been visited. – Risky actions include moving to a square that is not known to be deadly or OK. – Deadly actions are moving into a square that is known to have a pit or a Wumpus.
  • 56. Goal-based agents • Once the gold is found, it is necessary to change strategies. So now we need a new set of action values. • We could encode this as a rule: – (s) Holding(Gold,s)  GoalLocation([1,1]),s) • We must now decide how the agent will work out a sequence of actions to accomplish the goal. • Three possible approaches are: – Inference: good versus wasteful solutions – Search: make a problem with operators and set of states – Planning: to be discussed later