lecture_17
lecture_17
Outline
1 First Welfare Theorem
2 Preliminaries to Second Welfare Theorem
Past De…nitions
A feasible allocation (^x ; y^ ) is Pareto optimal if there is no other feasible
allocation (x; y ) such that
xi %i x^i for all i and xi i x
^i for some i:
L
An allocation (x ; y ) and a price vector p 2 R+ form a competitive
equilibrium if
1 for each j = 1; :::; J: p yj p yj for all yj 2 Yj ;
2 for each i = 1; :::; I : P
xi %i xi for all xi 2 fxi 2 Xi : p xi p ! i + j ij p yj g ; and
P P P P P P
3
i xi i !i + j yj and if Ii =1 xli < Ii =1 ! li + Jj=1 ylj then pl = 0.
x*
O1
First Welfare Theorem: Robinson Crusoe Example
Things seem easy
First Welfare Theorem: Counterexample
An Edgeworth Box Economy
Consider a two-person, two-good exchange economy.
a’s utility function Ua (x1a ; x2a ) = 7;
b’s utility function Ub (x1b ; x2b ) = x1b x2b .
The initial endowments are ! a = (2; 0) and ! b = (0; 2).
CLAIM: xa = (1; 1), xb = (1; 1), and prices p = (1; 1) form a competitive
equilibirum.
a’s utility is maximized.
b’s utility when her income equals 2 is maximized (this is a Cobb-Douglas utility
function with equal exponents, so spending half her income on each good is
optimal).
xa + xb = (2; 2) = ! a + ! b .
Is this allocation Pareto optimal? No:
x^a = (0; 0) and x^b = (2; 2) Pareto dominates xa , xb since consumer a has the
same utility while consumer b’s utility is higher.
De…nition
The preference relation %i on Xi is locally non-satiated if for every x in Xi and for
every " > 0 there exists an x 0 in Xi such that kx 0 xk < " and x 0 i x.
qP
L 2
Remember: ky zk = l =1 (yl zl ) is the Euclidean distance between
two points.
Remark
If %i is continuous and locally non-satiated there exist a locally non-satiated
utility function; then, any closed consumption set must be unbounded (or
there would be a global satiation point).
Local Non Satiation and Walrasian Demand
Lemma
Suppose %i is locally non-satiated, and let xi be de…ned as:
xi %i xi for all xi 2 fxi 2 Xi : p xi wi g :
Then
x i %i x i implies p xi wi
and
xi i xi implies p xi > wi
The theorem says that as far as Pareto optimality goes the social planner
cannot improve welfare upon a competitive equilibrium.
Conjecture
The theorem needs only a seemingly weak assumption to obtain a pretty strong
conclusion.
On the other hand, the important assumption of absence of externalities is
implicit in the way we set up the model.
An externality is present when preferences or pro…t depend on more than one’s
choices.
Externalities: An Example
An Edgeworth Box Economy
Consider a two-person, two-good exchange economy.
uA (x1A ; x2A ; x1B ) = x1A x2A x1B ; uB (x1B ; x2B ) = x1B x2B .
A su¤ers from B ’s consumption of the …rst good.
In the previous example, the …rst welfare theorem fails because A’s utility
depends on B’s consumption.
This is called a (negative) externality: the more B consumes of the good, the
worse-o¤ A becomes.
Among the assumptions implicit in our de…nition of preferences, one is
important for the …rst welfare theorem: there are no externalities in
consumption.
There can be also externalities in production.
Also, externalities can also be positive.
Competitive Equilibrium and the Core
Theorem
Any competitive equilibrium is in the core.
Proof.
Homework. This is very very similar to the proof of the First Welfare Theorem.
Picture
There is only one candidate price vector (the one tangent to both indi¤erence
curves).
However, this cannot work (B is not rich enough).
One can …x this by making B richer, giving her some money.
Equilibrium With Transfers
De…nition
Given an economy fXi ; %i ; ! i gi =1 ; fYj gj =1 , an allocation x ; y and a price
I J
= 0
Transfers redistribute income so that the ‘aggregate budget’balances.
This is important: in a general equilibirum model nothing should be ‘outside’
the economy
Second Welfare Theorem: Need Convex Preferences
and Production Sets
Pictures
Counterexample I to Second Welfare Theorem
Need convex preferences for the Second Welfare Theorem
x*
Í1
Í2
De…nition
In an exchange economy, an allocation x is supported by a non-zero price vector p
if: for each i = 1; :::; I
x 0 %i x i =) p x0 p xi
Picture
Counterexample III to Second Welfare Theorem
Make sure you see why this deals with the problem in the previous slide.
Any equilibrium with transfers is a quasi-equilibrium (make sure you check
Next Class